Skip to main content
Log in

Berg’s Answer to Frege’s Puzzle

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Berg seeks to defend the theory that the meaning of a proper name in a belief report is its reference against Frege’s puzzle by hypothesizing that when substituting coreferential names in belief reports results in reports that seem to have different truth values, the appearance is due to the fact that the reports have different metalinguistic implicatures. I review evidence that implicatures cannot be calculated in the way Grice or Berg imagine, and give reasons to believe that belief reports do not have the implicatures Berg attributes to them. I also argue that even if belief reports did have such implicatures, they would not explain why the belief reports in Frege’s puzzle seem to have different truth values. I point out that Berg has no reason to believe that Lois Lane believes Clark Kent is a reporter and Lois Lane believes Superman is a reporter are both true rather than both false, and that Leibniz’s Law cannot be used to defend substitutivity in belief reports because belief reports are not relational in the requisite way. Finally, I observe that some of the linguistic data Berg uses to argue for substitutivity in belief reports concerns the transparent interpretation of belief reports, whereas Frege’s puzzle concerns the opaque interpretation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I replaced Grice’s numerals with capital letters to avoid confusion with reference to display lines of this paper.

  2. See also Davis 2013, W. A Davis, Implicature, The Oxford handbook of pragmatics, accepted for publication; Lepore & Stone 2015.

  3. Grice’s conversational principles are: The Cooperative Principle (CP): Contribute what is required by the accepted purpose of the conversation; the maxim of Quality: Make your contribution true and justified; the maxim of Quantity: Be as informative as required; the maxim of Relation: Be relevant; the maxim of Manner: Be perspicuous.

  4. Cf. Miller (2015), who argues that the “Gricean rescue strategy” generally fails whenever the predictive failures of the semantic theory in question can be recast in epistemological or metaphysical terms.

  5. Berg also says that “well known observations by Keith Donnellan (1970), Saul Kripke (1972), David Kaplan (1978, 1979, 1989), and Hilary Putnam (1975) provide strong evidence for the natural view that the meaning of a proper name is nothing but the name’s bearer.” I have argued at length (Davis 2005) that the observations of these authors show that the meaning of a proper name is non-descriptive, but not that the meaning of a name is its referent.

  6. Many philosophers (e.g., Russell 1905) use ‘about’ relationally, so that nothing can be believes about nonexistent objects. In this sense, (41) is trivially valid but the premise is not a well-established fact, being true only if God actually exists.

  7. For a more adequate definition, see W. A. Davis, A Theory of Saying Reports, §9, in A. Capone, F. Kiefer, & F. Lo Piparo (Eds.), Indirect reports and pragmatics: Interdisciplinary Studies, accepted for publication, Cham: Springer.

  8. See also Grice 1989: 47–8; Levinson 1983: 97–100; 2000: 15; Horn 1989: 213–4; 2004: 20; Hazlett 2007; Huang 2014: 9–10.

References

  • Berg, J. (1988). The pragmatics of substitutivity. Linguistics and Philosophy, 11, 355–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, J. (1998). In defense of direct belief: substitutivity, availability, and iterability. Lingua e Stile, 33, 461–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, J. (2012). Direct belief: An essay on the semantics, pragmatics, and metaphysics of belief. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (1998). Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2003). Meaning, expression, and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2005). Nondescriptive meaning and reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2014) Implicature. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition), ed. E. N. Zalta. Palo Alto, CA. Http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/implicature/.

  • Davis, W. A. (2011). “Metalinguistic” negation, denials, and idioms. Journal of Pragmatics, 43, 2548–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2013). Grice’s razor and epistemic invariantism. Journal of Philosophical Research, 38, 147–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1999). Contextualism: An explanation and defense. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 187–205). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 126–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1970). Proper names and identifying descriptions. Synthese, 21, 335–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazlett, A. (2007). Grice’s razor. Metaphilosophy, 38, 669–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (2004). Implicature. In L. R. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics (pp. 3–28). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (2010). WJ-40: Issues in the investigation of implicature. In K. Petrus (Ed.), Meaning and analysis, new essays on Grice (pp. 310–339). Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Huang, Y. (2014). Pragmatics (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1978). Dthat. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, 9: Pragmatics (pp. 221–53). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1979). On the logic of demonstratives. In P. French, T. E. J. Uehling, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language (pp. 410–4). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry and H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355, 763–769). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Lepore, E., & Stone, M. (2015). Imagination and convention: distinguishing grammar and inference in language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, T. (1981). On proper names in belief ascriptions. Philosophical Studies, 39, 287–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Z. (2015). The reformulation argument: reining in Gricean pragmatics. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-015-0505-2.

  • Neale, S. (1992). Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 509–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2007). The evolutionary social psychology of off-record indirect speech acts. Intercultural Pragmatics, 4, 437–461.

  • Pinker, S., Nowak, M. A., and Lee, J. J. (2008). The logic of indirect speech. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 105, 833–838.

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning”. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Language, mind, and knowledge (pp. 131–93). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs, 35, 477–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wayne A. Davis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Davis, W.A. Berg’s Answer to Frege’s Puzzle. Philosophia 45, 19–34 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9631-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9631-5

Keywords

Navigation