Skip to main content
Log in

A Counterexample to the Uniqueness Thesis

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this essay, I present a straightforward counterexample to the Uniqueness Thesis, which holds, roughly speaking, that there is a unique rational response to any particular body of evidence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Ballantyne and Coffman (2012), Feldman (2006), (2007), Kelly (2005), (2010), (2013), and White (2005), (2013).

  2. For a recent sketch of various versions of Epistemic Instrumentalism, see Lockard (2013).

  3. See Brueckner and Bundy (2012), Kelly (2013).

  4. I believe it’s crucial to frame the thesis as holding that there is at most one rational attitude, as Feldman (2007) does, as opposed to holding that there is exactly one rational attitude, as White (2005), and those who follow his lead, have done. Here’s why. Take the following case, adapted from Kukla (1994). The Oracle decides to have a chat with the hare (from Aesop’s fable “The Tortoise and the Hare”), explaining to the hare the situation she is in. The Oracle convinces the hare of two conditionals: 1) If you believe that you will win the race, then you will not win the race, and 2) if you disbelieve that you will win the race, or suspend judgment on the matter, then you will win the race. Given that she has now been convinced of these two conditionals, the hare is in an awkward epistemic position. She knows ahead of time that if she believes that she will win, then this belief will be false, and thus such a belief is irrational to form. Similarly, if she believes she won’t win, or suspends judgment on the matter, then she knows that she will win, and so neither of these attitudes is rational to form. What must the hare do? It seems she must simply ignore the proposition ‘I will win the race’, since she is doomed if she forms any positive attitude about it. This example suggests that there are some cases where there is no rational attitude to take toward a proposition given a body of evidence, and therefore, the above formulation of Uniqueness is false. Of course, some might find this example controversial. But since the “at most one” version is logically weaker, it’s the preferable target. A counterexample to it brings down both versions.

  5. It’s at least plausible that the coarse-grained version is logically weaker, and thus it’s the more fitting target. Of course, there is some controversy here as well. But regardless, the same general strategy used later in the counterexample could easily be revised to apply to the fine-grained version as well.

  6. For example, if we were to plug these probabilities into Bayes’ Theorem, the credence the agent ought to have in the assessment of Trustworthy Weather is 0.5. See M. Titelbaum and M. Kopec, Plausible Permissivism, unpublished for the mathematical details.

  7. I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this case as a way to clarify exactly what the Trustworthy Principle entails.

  8. Because of this, we can’t simply plug the values into Bayes’ Theorem to yield a credence of 0.5 like we could in the case of Trustworthy vs. Reliable Weather.

  9. Thanks to Michael Goldsby for pressing this objection.

  10. Here I’m thinking of Kukla (1994) and, more recently, Greaves (2013) who uses such examples to put pressure on various views in the budding field of epistemic decision theory. I thank an anonymous referee for pointing out the latter connection.

References

  • Ballantyne, N., & Coffman, E. J. (2012). Conciliationism and uniqueness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 657–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner, A., & Bundy, A. (2012). On ‘epistemic permissiveness.’. Synthese, 188, 165–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2009). Disagreement as evidence: the epistemology of controversy. Philosophy Compass, 4, 756–767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. forthcoming. Conciliation, uniqueness and rational toxicity. Noûs

  • Feldman, R. (2006). Epistemological puzzles about disagreement. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology Futures (pp. 216–236). Oxford University Press.

  • Feldman, R. (2007). Reasonable religious disagreements. In L. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without Gods (pp. 194–214). Oxford University Press.

  • Greaves, H. (2013). Epistemic decision theory. Mind, 122, 915–952.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2005). The epistemic significance of disagreement. In J. Hawthorne & T. Gendler (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology (pp. 167–196). Oxford University Press.

  • Kelly, T. (2010). Peer disagreement and higher order evidence. In R. Feldman & T. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 111–174). Oxford University Press.

  • Kelly, T. (2013). Evidence can be permissive. In M. Steup, J. Turri, E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (pp. 298–312). Wiley.

  • Kukla, A. (1994). Some limits to empirical inquiry. Analysis, 54, 153–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lockard, M. (2013). Epistemic instrumentalism. Synthese, 190, 1701–1718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2005). Epistemic permissiveness. Philosophical Perspectives, 19, 445–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2013). Evidence Cannot Be Permissive. In M. Steup, J. Turri, E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (pp. 312–323). Wiley.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank John Basl, Michael Goldsby, and Michael Titelbaum for helpful discussion, as well as three anonymous referees for their suggestions and criticisms. This research was supported, in part, by the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation through their Sawyer Seminar entitled Theoretical Issues in Social Epistemology.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Kopec.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kopec, M. A Counterexample to the Uniqueness Thesis. Philosophia 43, 403–409 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-014-9579-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-014-9579-x

Keywords

Navigation