Skip to main content
Log in

Emergence, group judgment and the discursive dilemma

  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that the account of emergence advanced by Broad (The mind and its place in nature, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, (1925) is both defensible (in the sense that it provides a coherent and non-mysterious view that does what we want a theory of emergence to do) and applicable to some examples of group-level (or social) phenomena. Specifically, Broad’s account enables the formulation of a non-reductive physicalism (in philosophy of mind) or of a non-reductive individualism (in philosophy of social science), and correctly describes the case of group-judgment under the conditions of the discursive dilemma. Furthermore, this analysis shows that emergent phenomena need not be characterised using the resources of complexity theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although, interestingly, Mill does seem to hold something analogous to the non-reductive physicalist, or emergentist, view with regard to the inter-level relations between biology and chemistry and between chemistry and physics; for example, he regards vital phenomena as “heteropathic” effects of chemical causes, which violate the law of the Composition of Causes (see McLaughlin 1992, pp. 59–65).

  2. It is worth noting that, of Davidson’s three references to the concept of supervenience here, the first is for properties, the second is for events and the third is for objects. It is unclear from Davidson’s somewhat elliptical comment whether he intends this three-fold distinction to do any philosophical work, so in what follows, I shall ignore it.

  3. For those au fait with the literature in philosophy of mind, we might characterise (S1) as a “No zombies” clause, since it requires that physical duplicates will also be mental duplicates, and (S2) as a “No ghosts” clause, since it requires that mental events cannot be free-floating; they are somehow “anchored” in physical changes.

  4. Note that the physicalism (or individualism) that I have in mind here really is just an ontological physicalism. It’s a two-fold matter of controversy about whether (a) this is the correct way to formulate “physicalism” in general, and (b) whether, therefore, “non-reductive physicalism” (and its emergentist variant) is in fact committed to a kind of property or conceptual dualism. Chalmers (2006, p. 246), for example, claims that strong emergence “can be used to reject the physicalist picture of the world as fundamentally incomplete”, but seems to have in mind a version of physicalism that has both ontological and explanatory requirements. On this view, “non-reductive physicalism” is an oxymoron, and this is why Kim (1999, p. 5) describes it as an “inherently unstable halfway house.”

  5. For example, it is somewhat cringeworthy to read Broad (1925, p. 63) asserting, just a few short years before the formulation of the quantum mechanical explanation of chemical bonding, that “Nothing that we know about Hydrogen itself or in its combinations with anything but Oxygen would give us the least reason to expect that it would combine with Oxygen at all. And most of the chemical properties of water have no known connexion, either quantitative or qualitative, with those of Oxygen and Hydrogen. Here we have a clear instance where, so far as we can tell, the properties of a whole composed of two constituents could not have been predicted from a knowledge of the properties of those constituents…”.

  6. Of course, the discovery of laws (in physics, for example) is very often experimental. What’s significant here is that Broad’s trans-ordinal laws can only (his italics) be discovered experimentally.

  7. It’s important to note that Broad appears only to think of trans-ordinal laws either as biconditionals, or as statements of co-variation; he does not describe them as identity statements since the latter would render the discussion of dependence/supervenience superfluous, and would also make them explanatory in a way that would permit deducibility and thereby violate (B2).

  8. The relevant article states “The decision of the majority of the judges of the Supreme Court shall, for the purposes of this Article, be the decision of the Court and shall be pronounced by such one of those judges as the Court shall direct, and no other opinion, whether assenting or dissenting, shall be pronounced nor shall the existence of any such other opinion be disclosed”.

  9. The “solution” to the discursive dilemma as found in the Irish Constitution is, of course, not the only game in town. Ireland might equally have adopted a constitution that stipulated a premise-driven aggregation procedure; the judges would still count as judges at least in the sense that they would be asked to determine whether the defendant really had performed the action, and whether the contract really did forbid it.

References

  • Bedau M (1997) Weak emergence. Phil Perspect 11:375–399

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad CD (1925) The mind and its place in nature. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (2006) Strong and weak emergence. In: Clayton P, Davies P (eds) The re-emergence of emergence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (1980) Mental events. In his essays on actions and events. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim E (1897/2002) Suicide. (Trans. Spaulding JA, Simpson G) Routledge, London

  • Kim J (1982) Psychophysical supervenience. Philos Stud 41(January):51–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1991) Supervenience as a philosophical concept. Metaphilosophy 21(1–2):1–27

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1999) Making sense of emergence. Philos Stud 95:3–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List C, Pettit P (2006) Group agency and supervenience. South J Philos 44(S1):85–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List C, Pettit P (2011) Group agency. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin B (1992) The rise and fall of british emergentism. In: Beckermann A, Flohr H, Kim J (eds) Emergence or reduction?: Prospects for nonreductive physicalism. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1843/1875) A system of logic, vol 2, 9th edn. Longmans, Green, Reader and Dyer, London

  • Reynolds CW (1987) Flocks, herds and schools: a distributed behavioral model. In: Proceedings of the 14th annual conference on computer graphics and interactive techniques, SIGGRAPH’87:25–34. ACM, New York

  • Sawyer RK (2002) Durkheim’s dilemma: toward a sociology of emergence. Sociol Theor 20(2):227–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer RK (2003a) Nonreductive individualism: part I—supervenience and wild disjunction. Philos Soc Sci 32(4):537–559

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer RK (2003b) Nonreductive individualism: part II—social causation. Philos Soc Sci 33(2):203–224

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer RK (2005) Social emergence: societies as complex systems. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walmsley J (2010) Emergence and reduction in dynamical cognitive science. New Ideas Psychol 28:274–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks are due to audiences in Dublin, Cork and Cambridge for comments on earlier drafts of this paper, and especially to Tom Fitzsimons, Yakir Levin, Cathal O’Madagain, Robert Parker, David Papineau and two anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joel Walmsley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Walmsley, J. Emergence, group judgment and the discursive dilemma. Mind Soc 14, 185–201 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-015-0170-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-015-0170-3

Keywords

Navigation