Skip to main content
Log in

Why the Capacity to Pretend Matters for Empathy

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A phenomenological insight in the debate on empathy is that it is possible to directly perceive other people’s emotions in their expressive bodily behaviour. Contrary to what is suggested by many phenomenologists, namely that this perceptual skill is immediately available if one has vision, this paper argues that the perceptual skill for empathy is acquired. Such a skill requires that we have undergone certain emotional experiences ourselves and that we have had the experience of seeing the world differently, which is a form of pretence. By investigating how we retain knowledge of what is real while pretending, that is, how we anchor the experience of pretence in something that is not pretended, the paper argues that we split our experiential perspective into a double perspective, which differs from the cognitive act of understanding what a perspective is. With this notion in hand, we can return to the debate on empathy. It is argued that in order to have the capacity for direct empathic perception, one must have undergone experiences involving a double perspective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here it might help to think of the difference between pretending and mimicking: an actor can thus play a character without pretending to be him. To pretend to be Churchill comes with a voluntary act of decentring and with one’s own pretend kind of behaviour, whereas mimicking is guided by someone else’s actions or behaviour.

References

  • Currie G (1998) Pretence, pretending and metarepresenting. Mind Lang 13(1):33–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie G (2006) Rationality, decentring, and the evidence for pretence in non-human animals. In: Hurley S, Nudds M (eds) Rational animals?. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie G (2010) Narratives and narrators. A philosophy of stories. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Currie G, Ravencroft I (2002) Recreative minds. Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H, di Paolo E (2007) Enactive intersubjectivity: participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 6(4):485–507

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher H, di Paolo E, Gallagher S (2010) Can social interaction constitute social cognition. Trends Cognit Sci 14(10):441–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs T, De Jaegher H (2009) Enactive intersubjectivity: participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 8:465–486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2001) The practice of mind: theory, simulation or primary interaction? J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):83–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2005) How the body shapes the mind. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2008) Inference or interaction: social cognition without precursors. Philos Explor 11(3):163–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Hutto D (2008) Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspective on intersubjectivity. John Benhamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Zahavi D (2008) The phenomenological mind. An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris PL (2000) The work of the imagination. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1993) Sein und Zeit. Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M (2004) Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. WeltEndlichkeitEinsamkeit, Klostermann Seminar Ausgabe/Gesamt Ausgabe Band 29/30, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann

  • Leslie A (1987) Pretense and representation: the origins of ‘theory of mind’. Psychol Rev 94(4):412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie A (2000) ‘Theory of mind’ as a mechanism of selective attention. In: Gazzaniga M (ed) The new cognitive neurosciences. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1962) The phenomenology of perception. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael J (2011) Interactionism and mindreading. Rev Philos Psychol 2:559–578

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Stich SP (2000) A cognitive theory of pretence. Cognition 74(2):115–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Stich SP (2003) Mindreading. An integrated account of pretence, self-awareness, and understanding other minds. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J (1991) Understanding the representational mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J, Brandl JL, Garnham A (2003) What is a perspective problem? developmental issues in belief ascription and dual identity. Facta Philosophica 5:355–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe M (2012) Phenomenology as a form of empathy. Inquiry 5(55):473–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy V (2008) Do Infants know minds?. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler M (1973) Wesen und Formen der Sympathie. Francke Verlag, Bern

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding S (2010) Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind Lang 25(1):119–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2005) Subjectivity and selfhood. Investigating the first-person perspective. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2008) Simulation, projection and empathy. Conscious Cognit 17(2):514–522

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for the questions and helpful comments made by two anonymous reviewers. Further, I am indebted to the following for their valuable comments and suggestions on earlier versions of the paper: Johan Gersel, Dorothée Legrand, Dylan Trigg, Thomas Schwarz Wentzer, Kasper Lysemose, Rasmus Dyring and the research group for Philosophical Hermeneutics at Aarhus University. Finally, this research is funded by The Danish Council for Independent Research supporting the research project “Existential Anthropology: Inquiring Human Responsiveness” at Aarhus University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Line Ryberg Ingerslev.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ingerslev, L.R. Why the Capacity to Pretend Matters for Empathy. Topoi 33, 201–213 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9202-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9202-y

Keywords

Navigation