Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Causation in Personal Injury Law: The Case for a Probabilistic Approach

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper makes the case for a wider acceptance of a probabilistic approach to causation in negligence. This acceptance would help to remove much of the incoherence which has come to afflict the English law of personal injury law. This incoherence can also be found in other common law jurisdictions (notably those of the United States, Canada and Australia). Concentrating upon recent UK case law, the argument opposes the contention that ‘naked statistics’ can play no role in establishing causation. The argument is controversial but it can be reduced to three unremarkable grounds: (1) With its acceptance (albeit in certain carefully prescribed circumstances) of liability for a negligently increased risk which has eventuated, the common law has already embraced a probabilistic conception of causation; (2) The English common law already employs a probabilistic (frequentist) approach to identifying coincidences; and (3) With the ‘balance of probabilities’ as the standard of proof in civil cases, the common law has long had a probabilistic (epistemic) concept at its core. Probabilistic approaches (at both the type and token level) are shown to be consistent with laypersons’ understanding of the concepts such as risk, chance, odds and likelihood. Moreover, a wider acceptance of a probabilistic perspective on causation would entail no major challenge to the fundamental aims of tort, viz. deterrence and corrective justice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Gregg v Scott [2005] UKHL 2, para. 79.

  2. Fairchild v Glenhaven Funeral Services Ltd, Fox v Spousal (Midlands) Ltd, Matthews v Associated Portland Cement Manufacturers (1978) Ltd and others [2002] UKHL 22.

  3. [1973] 1 W. L. R. 1.

  4. [2006] UKHL 20.

  5. Karen Sienkiewicz (Administratrix of the Estate of Enid Costello Deceased) v Greif (UK) Ltd [2011] UKSC 10.

  6. Lord Brown, ibid, para. 174.

  7. Lord Bingham, in Fairchild, above n 2 at para. 39, articulated six conditions which had to be met before liability could be based on an increased and materialised risk. Of these six, the most important for our purposes are the ‘rock of uncertainty’ and the requirement that all sources of risk must be, if not identical, substantially similar.

  8. Above n 5, para. 143.

  9. [1987] A. C. 750.

  10. Mallett v Monagle [1970] A. C. 166, 176.

  11. Davies v. Taylor [1974] A. C. 207, 212–213.

  12. Above n 9, 786.

  13. Herskovits v. Group Health Cooperative of Puget Sound (1983) 664 P. 2d 474.

  14. Above n 9, 790.

  15. Above n 5, para. 30.

  16. Ibid, para. 96.

  17. Ibid.

  18. Ibid, para. 91.

  19. Ibid, para. 156.

  20. Ibid, para. 163.

  21. Ibid, para. 161.

  22. Ibid. para. 170.

  23. Ibid, para. 164.

  24. ibid, para. 217.

  25. Chester v Afshar [2005] 1 AC 134.

  26. Above n 1.

  27. Ibid, para. 155. The error lay in failing to understand the role of ‘resilience’ in a counterfactual, see further C. Miller (2005).

References

  • Dowe P (2000) Physical Causation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eells E (1991) probabilistic Causality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geddes DM (1979) The Natural history of lung cancer: a review based on rates of tumour growth 73 British Journal of Diseases of the Chest 1

  • Gold S (1986) Causation in toxic torts: Burdens of Proof, Standards of Persuasion, and Statistical Evidence 96 Yale Law Journal 376

  • Hart HLA, Honoré T (1959) Causation in the Law, 1st edn. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA, Honoré T (1985) Causation in the Law, 2nd edn. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hill AB (1965) The environment and disease: association or causation? 58 Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine 295

  • Hitchcock C (2007) Prevention, Preemption, and the Principle of sufficient reason 116 Philosophical Review 495

  • Humphreys P (1989) The chances of explanation: causal explanation in the social, medical, and physical sciences. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK (1986) Philosophical papers, vol ll. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor DH (2005) Probability: a philosophical introduction. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzies P (1996) Probabilistic causation and the pre-emption problem 105 Mind 85

  • Miller C (2005) Gregg v Scott: loss of chance revisited 4 Law, Probability and Risk 227

  • Miller C (2012) Negligent failure to warn: why is it so difficult? 28 Journal of Professional Negligence 266

  • Reece H (1996) Losses of Chances in the Law 59 Modern Law Review 188

  • Russell B (1913) On the Notion of Cause 13 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 1

  • Sober E, Papineau D (1986) Causal factors, causal inference, causal explanation 60 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 97

  • Stapleton J (2006) Occam’s Razor Reveals an Orthodox Basis for Chester v Afshar 122 Law Quarterly Review 426

  • Stapleton J (2008) Choosing What We Mean by ‘Causation’ in the Law 73 Missouri Law Review 433

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright RW (1985) Causation in Tort Law 73 California Law Review 1735

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is grateful for the many helpful comments of the Editors and the reviewer of an earlier draft. He also acknowledges his debt to the Leverhulme Trust for the award of an Emeritus Research Fellowship which has enabled him to continue his research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Miller.

Appendix: Lewis’s Principal Principle

Appendix: Lewis’s Principal Principle

Let C represent some credibility function (epistemic probability) that, at time t, some event A will occur, and that X is the proposition that A had an objective chance of x. E is any proposition compatible with X that is admissible at time t. Then according to Lewis (1986: 87):

$$ {\text{C}}({\text{A}}|{\text{XE}}) $$

For the purposes of this article, suppose X is the proposition that A has a chance x at time t of being the cause of some injury, and E is the overall evidence which is compatible with X, then the above equation relates belief probability to objective chance. Lewis (ibid.) further explains that if the evidence E supports a very high degree of belief in X, that is, that the objective chance of A is causal truly is x, then C(X|E) is very close to one, then it follows that the unconditional epistemic probability that A is causal C(A|E) = x. (By unconditional, we mean conditional only on the existence of that evidence E which persuades us the truth of X.) Only when the fact-finder in a trial has this high degree of confidence in the evidence, can she allow the objective chance to ‘fix’ her epistemic probability in the truth of the causal proposition A, which she then gauges against the BOP standard.

Lewis emphasises that X is ‘the proposition that the chance, at time t, of A’s holding equals x… [and with x, he is] speaking of objective, single-case chance—not credence, not frequency’ (1986: 90). His aim is to relate this token probability to some credence that X will obtain conditional upon the degree of belief in x. In contrast, Sober’s ‘connecting principle’ (1986: 101) assumes the existence of a population, of cause events C and of effect events E, from which a type probability can be measured. The closer this type probability is to 1.0 (that is, the fewer the instances of the effect arising in the absence of the cause), the greater the support for the hypothesis that a single C event at time t1 token-caused a single E event at t2. Clearly, under either principle, the lower the estimate of the token probability, the less secure is any claim that one token event was the cause of another.

Philosophy aside, if all the other conditions of the Fairchild exception are satisfied, a negligently increased risk (objective chance) of x < 0.5 should, if it has eventuated in injury, incur liability.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Miller, C. Causation in Personal Injury Law: The Case for a Probabilistic Approach. Topoi 33, 385–396 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9181-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9181-z

Keywords

Navigation