1 Introduction

We often do not know the probabilities of uncertain events when making decisions. Research has shown that attitudes towards uncertainty do not just differ between individuals, but also depend on the source of the uncertainty (Abdellaoui et al. 2011). For example, people prefer to bet on sources for which they feel competent rather than on sources for which they feel incompetent (Heath and Tversky 1991; Keppe and Weber 1995; Tversky and Fox 1995; de Lara Resende and Wu 2010). It has been argued that such a preference can partially explain the home bias in financial markets, defined as the tendency of investors to hold nearly all their wealth in domestic assets despite the benefits of international diversification (French and Poterba 1991; Kilka and Weber 2000; Uppal and Wang 2003).

Preferences over different sources of uncertainty can be modeled through source-dependent utility functions, as axiomatized by Cappelli et al. (2016). Chew et al. (2008) investigated and found support for source-dependent utility in a neuroimaging experiment. Various models have been proposed in which the agent faces two consecutive stages of uncertainty and has a different utility function for each stage (Nau 2006; Ergin and Gul 2009; Strzalecki 2011).

In the present paper, we propose simple behavioral definitions of comparative uncertainty aversion of a single agent towards different sources of uncertainty.Footnote 1 We build on Yaari’s (1969) seminal definition of comparative uncertainty aversion and purely rely on the agent’s willingness to accept bets under each source.Footnote 2 Our definitions do not require that the agent’s choices satisfy subjective expected utility (SEU), but allow for comparative statements regarding the agent’s utility curvature if they do.

Our results follow directly from Yaari’s mathematical result. Conceptually, however, they remove two fundamental limitations. Yaari’s condition allows for the comparison of uncertainty aversion of a single agent across different situations, but only if the agent (1) faces the exact same events and (2) holds the same beliefs regarding the likelihood of these events across the two situations. These limitations make Yaari’s definition inapplicable for most studies of source preference, which typically involve different events or different information levels about these events. By removing these two limitations, our conditions not only allow for the comparison of uncertainty aversion of a single agent towards different sources, they also open up further possibilities to investigate the effects of learning and situational factors on uncertainty preferences, and to compare uncertainty aversion between agents.

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 introduces the theoretical framework and presents our main definition for binary acts. Section 3 extends our definition to general acts. Section 4 shows how our definitions can be applied to investigate ambiguity aversion in Klibanoff et al.’s (2005) smooth ambiguity model, to study the effects of learning and the decision situation on uncertainty preferences, and to compare preferences between agents. Section 5 concludes.

2 Main result

We compare an agent’s uncertainty aversion to two sources indexed by \(j\in \{A,B\}\). Let a source of uncertainty \(S_j\) be a finite or infinite state space containing all states of nature s pertaining to j. The agent does not know which state of \(S_j\) is true. It is possible to consider a compound state space \(S_A \times S_B\), but we do not need it for our main results. An event E is a subset of \(S_j\). Let the set of events of \(S_j\) considered by the agent be a sigma-algebra denoted as \(\Sigma _j\). The complementary event of E is denoted as \(E^c\). The outcome set is X, an open interval of the reals. The agents can choose between acts, which are finite \(\Sigma _j\)-measurable mappings from \(S_j\) to X. Acts are typically denoted f or g and the set of all acts on \(S_j\) is \({\mathcal {F}}_j\). The bet \(x_Ey\) is a binary act yielding outcome x, if event E occurs, and y, otherwise. When \(x>y\), we call \(x_Ey\) a bet on E and \(y_Ex\) a bet against E. Acts that yield the same outcome z for all \(s\in S_j\) are referred to as z.

The agents have preferences \(\succsim _j\) over \({\mathcal {F}}_j\), with \(\sim _j\), \(\succ _j\), \(\prec _j\), and \(\precsim _j\) defined as usual. We will say that \(\succsim _j\) is represented by subjective expected utility (SEU) if there exists a countably additive subjective probability measure \(P_j\) and a utility function \(u_j\) uniquely defined up to an affine transformation such that \(f\succsim _j g\) \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(\int _{S_j} P_j(s)u_j(f(s))\mathrm{d}s\ge \int _{S_j} P_j(s)u_j(g(s))\mathrm{d}s\). Throughout, we assume that the utility is continuous and strictly increasing. We say that \(u_A\) is more concave than \(u_B\) if there exists a concave function \(\varphi \) such that \(u_A=\varphi \circ u_B\). Finally, \(P_j\) is nonatomic if for all \(E\in \Sigma _j\) such that \(P_j(E)>0\), there exists \(F\in \Sigma _j\) such that \(F\subset E\) and \(0<P_j(F)<P_j(E)\). Nonatomicity is guaranteed by Savage’s (1954) axiomatization of SEU.

Yaari (1969) defined comparative uncertainty aversion in terms of the agent’s willingness to accept bets. His definition states that an agent is more uncertainty-averse in one situation than in another, if his acceptance set in the former situation is a subset of his acceptance set in the latter. Under SEU, this implies that the agent has more concave utility in the former situation than in the latter. For this definition to be meaningful, it is necessary that the agent (1) faces the same events and (2) holds the same beliefs regarding the likelihood of these events across the two situations. We propose an alternative way to compare uncertainty attitudes, which removes these constraints. The main point of our result is simple: to compare uncertainty aversion, one should not only consider bets on events, but also bets against them.

Consider two events: \(E\in \Sigma _A\) and \(F\in \Sigma _B\). Imagine that the agent is willing to accept a bet on E (\(x_Ey\)), but not on F (\(x_Fy\)). This can either be because the agent is more uncertainty-averse towards source \(S_B\) than she is towards source \(S_A\), or because she believes that event E is more likely than event F. Beliefs, however, are unable to explain why the agent would simultaneously prefer bets on E to bets on F and prefer bets on \(E^c\) to bets on \(F^c\). This logic leads to the following condition for the agent to be more uncertainty-averse towards source \(S_B\) than towards source \(S_A\): whenever the agent would reject a bet \(x_Ey\) and its symmetric bet \(y_Ex\), she should always reject either \(x_Fy\) or \(y_Fx\), possibly both.

Theorem 1

Assume that \(\succsim _A\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(\succsim _B\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_B\) are represented by subjective expected utility. The following statement (i) is necessary for statement (ii). It is also sufficient if there exist \(E\in \Sigma _A\) and \(F\in \Sigma _B\) such that \(P_A(E)=P_B(F)=\frac{1}{2}\).

  1. (i)

    \(\forall \) \(E\in \Sigma _A,\) \(F\in \Sigma _B,\) and xy,  and z in X

    \((z\succsim _A x_Ey \text { and } z\succsim _A y_Ex)\) \(\Rightarrow \) \(( z\succsim _B x_Fy \text { or } z\succsim _B y_Fx)\).

  2. (ii)

    \(u_B\) is more concave than \(u_A\).

Statement (i) is necessary and sufficient to compare the agent’s utility towards two sources of uncertainty if there is at least one event under each source to which the agent assigns probability \(\frac{1}{2}\). Using Ramsey’s (1931) concept of ethically neutral events, we only need one ethically neutral event under each source. This richness condition is automatically satisfied if \(P_A\) and \(P_B\) are nonatomic, as follows from Savage’s (1954) axiomatization.

Corollary 1

If,  in Theorem 1, \(P_A\) and \(P_B\) are nonatomic,  then (i) is equivalent to (ii).

Ergin and Gul (2009) and Strzalecki (2011) call being more uncertainty-averse to one source than to another second-order risk aversion and propose preference conditions to characterize it. Unlike in Ergin and Gul (2009), our condition does not use concepts from the representation we assume. Unlike in Strzalecki (2011), our condition does not require the existence of acts whose outcomes depend on both sources of uncertainty.

Cappelli et al. (2016) proposed a condition for source preference based on utility midpoints. Such endogenous midpoints can be measured by techniques proposed by Abdellaoui et al. (2007), Fishburn and Edwards (1997), Ghirardato et al. (2003), Harvey (1986), Köbberling and Wakker (2003), and Vind (2003). Yet, they are more complex than the modification of Yaari’s intuitive technique proposed here.

Kopylov (2016) proposed a condition with the same structure as condition (i) in Theorem 1 but in a (Anscombe–Aumann) setting where acts are mappings from the state space to lotteries. His condition drops the second limitation of Yaari’s condition (same beliefs), but still suffers from the first limitation by requiring that the same events are considered before and after the implication symbol. Condition (i) generalizes it such that the events can differ and potentially stem from different sources.

Our definition allows for the ranking of sources of uncertainty on the basis of the agent’s uncertainty aversion towards each source. It allows for comparing utility between different sources and, thereby, complements the definitions of Tversky and Wakker (1995), which allowed for comparing decision weights between sources in non-expected utility models.Footnote 3

3 Extensions to general acts

To extend the definition from bets to general acts, we can consider what happens to two events only for each agent and keep everything else (what happens on the other events) constant. Theorem 2 applies this approach. We denote \(x_{E}y_{F}f\) the act yielding x on E, y on F, and f(s) for all \(s\notin E\cup F\).

Theorem 2

Assume that \(\succsim _A\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(\succsim _B\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_B\) are represented by subjective expected utility. The following statement (i) is necessary for statement (ii). It is also sufficient if there exist \(E,F\in \Sigma _A\) and \(G,H\in \Sigma _B\) such that \(P_A(E)=P_A(F)\) and \(P_B(G)=P_B(H)\).

  1. (i)

    \(\forall \) \(E,F\in \Sigma _A,\) \(G,H\in \Sigma _B,\) \(f\in {\mathcal {F}}_A,\) \(g\in {\mathcal {F}}_B,\) and xy,  and z in X

    \((z_{E \cup F}f \succsim _A x_{E}y_{F}f\quad \text { and } \quad z_{E \cup F}f \succsim _A y_{E}x_{F}f)\)

    \(\Rightarrow (z_{G \cup H}g \succsim _B x_{G}y_{H}g \quad \text { or } \quad z_{G \cup H}g \succsim _B y_{G}x_{H}g)\).

  2. (ii)

    \(u_B\) is more concave than \(u_A\).

Note that we have weakened the richness requirement on the state spaces: it is still necessary that there are two events that the agent finds equally likely under each source, but these events no longer have to be complementary.

In statement (i) of both Theorems 1 and 2, we permuted two outcomes. We can also permute all outcomes of the act. Consider \(f\in {\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(g\in {\mathcal {F}}_B\), with \(f=(E_1:x_1,\ldots ,E_n:x_n)\) and \(g=(F_1:x_1,\ldots ,F_n:x_n)\). Hence, f and g yield the same n outcomes, but need not assign these outcomes to the same events. Let \(\Pi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) denote a permutation of \((x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\). For simplicity, we use the \(\Pi (f)\) to denote the act assigning \(\Pi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) to \((E_1,\ldots ,E_n)\) and \(\Pi (g)\) to denote the same permutation of the outcome of g.

Theorem 3

Assume that \(\succsim _A\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(\succsim _B\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_B\) are represented by subjective expected utility. The following statement (i) is necessary for statement (ii). It is also sufficient if there exist,  for some integer n,  an n-fold partitions \(\{E_i\}_n\) of \(S_A\) and an n-fold partition \(\{F_i\}_n\) of \(S_B,\) such that \(P_A(E_i)=P_B(F_i)=\frac{1}{n}\) for all \(i\in \{1,\ldots ,n\}\).

  1. (i)

    \(\forall \) \(f\in {\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(g\in {\mathcal {F}}_B\) yielding the same outcomes \((x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) and for all \(z\in X,\)

    \((z\succsim _A \Pi (f) \quad \forall \Pi )\) \(\Rightarrow \) \((\exists \Pi \text { such that } z\succsim _B \Pi (g))\).

  2. (ii)

    \(u_B\) is more concave than \(u_A\).

We can also decide not to consider all permutations, but only a subset of permutations that “maximally differ” from each other. We can do so by using a type of permutation that we will call cyclic. Consider an act \(f=(E_1:x_1,E_2:x_2,\ldots ,E_{n-1}:x_{n-1},E_n:x_n)\). Let \(\pi \) be a cyclic permutation function, defined as \(\pi (f)=(E_1:x_2,E_2:x_3,\ldots ,E_{n-1}:x_n,E_n:x_1)\). It moves each outcome one event to the left. We denote \(\pi ^m\) the compound function that applies \(\pi \) m times. For instance, \(\pi ^3=\pi \circ \pi \circ \pi \).

Theorem 4

Assume that \(\succsim _A\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(\succsim _B\) defined over \({\mathcal {F}}_B\) are represented by subjective expected utility. The following statement (i) is necessary for statement (ii). It is also sufficient if there exist,  for some integer n,  an n-fold partitions \(\{E_i\}_n\) of \(S_A\) and an n-fold partition \(\{F_i\}_n\) of \(S_B,\) such that \(P_A(E_i)=P_B(F_i)=\frac{1}{n}\) for all \(i\in \{1,\ldots ,n\}\).

  1. (i)

    \(\forall \) \(f\in {\mathcal {F}}_A\) and \(g\in {\mathcal {F}}_B\) yielding the same outcomes \((x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) and for all \(z\in X,\)

    \((z\succsim _A \pi ^m(f) \quad \forall m\in \{1,\ldots ,n\})\) \(\Rightarrow \) \((\exists m\in \{1,\ldots ,n\} \text { such that } z\succsim _B \pi ^m(g))\).

  2. (ii)

    \(u_B\) is more concave than \(u_A\).

In Theorems 3 and 4, the additional requirement for (i) to be sufficient for (ii) is stronger than that of Theorem 2. The approach of Theorem 2 is, therefore, the least demanding in terms of richness of the state spaces and beliefs of the agents. For all the three theorems, the requirements are trivially satisfied by nonatomic probability measures.

Corollary 2

If,  in Theorems 2, 3, and 4, \(P_A\) and \(P_B\) are nonatomic,  then (i) is equivalent to (ii).

4 Further applications

Until now, our theory has focused on a single agent facing different sources of uncertainty. Our results, however, also open up further possibilities to investigate ambiguity aversion in Klibanoff et al.’s (2005) smooth ambiguity model, to study the effect of learning on uncertainty preferences, to study how the decision situation affects preferences, and to compare preferences between agents. Here, we will briefly discuss these applications.

4.1 Application 1: Smooth ambiguity model

Ambiguity aversion can be seen as a special case of source preference. If one of the two sources of uncertainty that an agent faces is risky (known probabilities), then ambiguity aversion can be defined as being more averse towards the uncertain source than to the risky one. In his seminal work, Ellsberg (1961) provides convincing examples suggesting that individuals will prefer to bet on risk rather than uncertainty. In his simplest example, people prefer to bet on an urn with 50 red and 50 black balls over an urn containing a 100 balls that are either red or black in unknown proportions, irrespective of the winning color. While Ellsberg presented this as a thought experiment, subsequent work has convincingly shown his intuition to be correct (Camerer and Weber 1992).

We now show how our condition can be applied to study ambiguity aversion in the smooth ambiguity model introduced by Klibanoff et al. (2005). In their setup, the state space is the compound of a separable metric space \(S_B\) and a probability interval \(S_A=(0,1]\). Hence, \(S=S_A \times S_B\). Let \(\Sigma _A\) and \(\Sigma _B\) be the Borel sigma-algebra of \(S_A\) and \(S_B\), respectively, and define \(\Sigma =\Sigma _A\otimes \Sigma _B\). The set of all countably additive probability measures over \(\Sigma \) that are congruent with the Lebesgue measure over \(S_A\) is denoted \(\Delta \). Let \({\mathcal {F}}\) be the set of all acts on S. An act is a lottery if it only depends on \(S_A\) and we denote \(\mathcal {L}\) the set of lotteries. We denote \(x_py\) the lottery \(x_{E\times S_B}y\) when the Lebesgue measure of E is p. The agent’s preferences \(\succsim \) are represented by the smooth ambiguity model if there exist a utility function u, a function \(\varphi \) defined over the image of u and a probability measure over \(\Delta \) such that \(f\succsim g\) is equivalent to \(\int _{\Delta }\varphi (\int _S u(f)\mathrm{d}P)\mathrm{d}\mu \ge \int _{\Delta }\varphi (\int _S u(g)\mathrm{d}P)\mathrm{d}\mu \). We assume that the functions \(\varphi \) and u are continuous and strictly increasing.

Theorem 5

Assume \(\succsim \) is represented by the smooth ambiguity model. The following statement (i) is necessary for statement (ii). It is also sufficient if there exists \(E\in \Sigma \) such that \(\int _{\Delta }P(E)\mathrm{d}\mu =\frac{1}{2}\).

  1. (i)

    \(\forall \) \(p\in [0,1],\) \(F\in \Sigma ,\) and xy,  and z in X

    \((z\succsim _A x_py \text { and } z\succsim _A y_px )\) \(\Rightarrow \) \(( z\succsim _B x_Fy \text { or } z\succsim _B y_Fx ).\)

  2. (ii)

    \(\varphi \) is concave.

Our condition allows us to characterize the concavity of \(\varphi \) without using unobservable acts mapping \(\Delta \) to X unlike Baillon et al. (2012), and without using u or \(\mu \) in the preference condition unlike Klibanoff et al. (2005).

4.2 Application 2: Learning

Consider an agent who has the possibility to learn about a single source S (e.g., to receive signals). Will she become less uncertainty-averse after learning more about the uncertainty she faces? If she is Bayesian, she should update her beliefs based on the information she receives and we could not use Yaari’s original definition to compare her utility before and after receiving information. By contrast, denote \(\succsim _B\) her preferences Before receiving information and \(\succsim _A\) her preferences After receiving information. Theorems 14 allow us to study the effect of learning on her uncertainty aversion and on her utility curvature.

Observation 1

Theorems 14 can be used to compare an agent’s utility curvature before and after receiving information about S.

4.3 Application 3: Situational factors

In a similar vein, Yaari’s definition does not allow for the comparison of an agent’s utility curvature in different situations (decision context, material conditions, time pressure, etc.) if the agent’s beliefs differ between them. It will often be difficult to rule out the possibility that beliefs are affected by situational factors, especially if these factors are influential enough to affect preferences. Theorems 14 allow for the study of situational influences on preferences, even if beliefs are also affected.

Observation 2

Theorems 14 can be used to compare an agent’s utility curvature between different situations,  irrespective of whether these situations affect the agent’s beliefs.

An example of such a situational factor is the weather. It has been found that the weather affects traders’ behavior, with market returns being lower on cloudy days (Saunders 1993; Hirshleifer and Shumway 2003). It is not clear whether this is because it affects traders’ perceived likelihood of future events or because it affects their intrinsic willingness to bear uncertainty. Watson and Funck (2012) showed that short selling by (professional) traders increases on cloudy days, suggesting that they are more willing to bet against stocks going up. In the light of our definition, this suggests that the impact of cloudiness on stock returns is caused by a change in beliefs, rather than a higher degree of uncertainty aversion.

4.4 Application 4: Different agents

So far, we have focused on comparing uncertainty aversion of a single agent across different situations. The main focus of Yaari’s (1969) original definition was to compare uncertainty aversion between different agents. To do this, however, agents needed to face the same events and their subjective probabilities should coincide. Especially, this latter requirement is overly restrictive as it denies uncertainty its fundamental property of potential disagreement on beliefs; requiring all agents to hold the same beliefs effectively reduces uncertainty to risk. Theorems 14 can also be used if \(\succsim _A\) and \(\succsim _B\) belong to different actors. As such, they can be used to compare preferences between agents who hold different beliefs or face different events entirely.

Observation 3

Theorems 14 can be used to compare the utility curvature between different agents,  possibly facing different events from different sources of uncertainty.

Comparing utility curvature when beliefs differ can alternatively be obtained from requirements about endogenous midpoints as shown by Baillon et al. (2012). However, such midpoints are more complex to be observed than our modifications of Yaari’s intuitive technique.

The ability to compare uncertainty preferences between agents facing different sources of uncertainty can be of great practical value in cross-cultural research. Consider comparing uncertainty preferences towards the stock market for investors from different countries. One option would be to compare their uncertainty preferences on a single market, such as the Dow Jones. However, such a market will potentially have a different meaning for investors from different countries. It will often be more informative to compare the investors’ willingness to take risk on markets that carry similar meaning to them, such as their respective home markets.

5 Conclusion and discussion

We have introduced behavioral definitions of comparative uncertainty aversion for a single agent towards different sources of uncertainty. Our definitions generalize Yaari’s (1969) intuitive definition of comparative uncertainty aversion and only depend on the agent’s willingness to accept bets under each source. Although they do not require that the agent’s choices satisfy subjective expected utility (SEU), our definitions allow for comparative statements regarding the agent’s utility curvature towards each source if they do.

Our generalizations also open up new possibilities to investigate ambiguity aversion in Klibanoff et al.’s (2005) smooth ambiguity model, to study the effects of learning and situational factors on uncertainty preferences, and to compare uncertainty preferences between different agents.

Yaari (1969) already wrote that the major use of measures of risk aversion is to facilitate empirical applications. We hope that our definitions will facilitate the growing study of the rich domain of uncertainty.