Skip to main content
Log in

Implementing equal division with an ultimatum threat

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“Practically speaking, why threaten such punishment if the threat is likely to be empty and there are, moreover, ‘softer’ ways of inducing reasonable behavior?” (Brams and Taylor 1996, p. 173)

Abstract

We modify the payment rule of the standard divide the dollar (DD) game by introducing a second stage and thereby resolve the multiplicity problem and implement equal division of the dollar in equilibrium. In the standard DD game, if the sum of players’ demands is less than or equal to a dollar, each player receives what he demanded; if the sum of demands is greater than a dollar, all players receive zero. We modify this second part, which involves a harsh punishment. In the modified game \((D\!D^{\prime })\), if the demands are incompatible, then players have one more chance. In particular, they play an ultimatum game to avoid the excess. In the two-player version of this game, there is a unique subgame perfect Nash equilibrium in which players demand (and receive) an equal share of the dollar. We also provide an \(n\)-player extension of our mechanism. Finally, the mechanism we propose eliminates not only all pure strategy equilibria involving unequal divisions of the dollar, but also all equilibria where players mix over different demands in the first stage.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Schelling’s (1960) argument is based on the prominence of 50–50 division. Arguments in Sugden (1986), Young (1993), Skyrms (1996), and Bolton (1997) are based on evolutionary accounts.

  2. Equal treatment of equals: any two players with equal demands should receive the same amount. Efficiency: if the sum of demands exceeds the estate, the estate should be completely distributed. Order preservation of awards: a player with a higher demand should not receive a lower amount than a player with a lower demand.

  3. Claims monotonicity: a player should not receive a lower amount after increasing his demand. Non-bossiness: a change in a player’s demand should not be able to change other players’ payoffs, if this change does not influence his own payoff.

  4. Harsanyi (1977), Howard (1992), and Miyagawa (2002) are some other studies that implement the Nash bargaining solution in subgame perfect equilibrium with sequential game forms.

  5. We thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing Malueg (2010) to our attention and suggesting an alternative proof, which also considers mixed strategies (Theorem 2).

  6. To keep the paper simple, reader-friendly and comparable to Brams and Taylor (1994) and Anbarcı (2001), we intentionally used actions as the working horse instead of strategies.

  7. The following arguments—explicitly or implicity—use the fact that sequential rationality implies acceptance of any offer in the second stage.

  8. The subcase, \(d_{2}<1/2\), is not analyzed here since it is trivial and analyzed in Theorem 1.

  9. We assume that players mix over only the Borel measurable subsets of \([0,1]\) . Also note that since players utility functions are linear they are Borel measurable.

  10. Note that it is sufficient to check the best response of a player against a mixing opponent.

  11. For simplicity, we assume that \(F\) is an absolutely continuous function, which implies that there exists a Lebesgue-integrable function \(f\) equal to the derivative of \(F\) almost everywhere. Moreover, this \(f\) is called the density function. Note that, alternatively \(F\) can be assumed to be continuous and have a derivative almost everywhere, which would then imply that there exists a Henstock–Kurzweil integrable \(f\) (Bartle 2001, Theorem 4.7).

  12. Note that when \(n=2\), it is not necessary to assume \(x_{i}\in [0,d_{i}]\) since \(x_{i}>d_{i}\) is not possible.

  13. As in Theorem 2, we assume that players mix over only the Borel measurable subsets of \([0,1]\).

  14. As in Theorem 2, for simplicity, we assume that \(F\) is an absolutely continuous function.

References

  • Anbarcı, N. (2001). Divide-the-dollar game revisited. Theory and Decision, 50, 295–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreozzi, L. (2010). An evolutionary theory of social justice: Choosing the right game. European Journal of Political Economy, 26, 320–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashlagi, I., Karagözoğlu, E., & Klaus, B. (2012). A non-cooperative support for equal division in estate division problems. Mathematical Social Sciences, 63, 228–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartle, R. G. (2001). A modern theory of integration. Graduate studies in mathematics (Vol. 32). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1998). Game theory and the social contract II. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, D. E. (1981). Is arbitration really compatible with bargaining? Industrial Relations, 20, 233–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, G. E. (1997). The rationality of splitting equally. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 32, 365–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Taylor, A. E. (1994). Divide the dollar: Three solutions and extensions. Theory and Decision, 37, 211–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brams, S. J., & Taylor, A. E. (1996). Fair division: From cake-cutting to dispute resolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. (1977). Rational behavior and bargaining in games and social situations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, J. (1992). A social choice rule and its implementation in perfect equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory, 56, 142–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karagözoǧlu, E. (2012). Bargaining games with joint production. In G. E. Bolton & R. T. A. Croson (Eds.), Oxford handbook of economic conflict resolution (Chap. 24, pp. 359–372). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Kilgour, M. (2003). Game models of negotiation and arbitration. Encyclopedia of life support systems. Oxford, UK: EOLSS Publishers.

  • Malueg, D. A. (2010). Mixed strategy equilibria in the Nash demand game. Economic Theory, 44, 243–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miyagawa, E. (2002). Subgame-perfect implementation of bargaining solutions. Games and Economic Behavior, 41, 292–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. (1991). Game theory: Analysis of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. (1953). Two-person cooperative games. Econometrica, 21, 128–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nydegger, R. V., & Owen, G. (1975). Two person bargaining: An experimental test of Nash axioms. International Journal of Game Theory, 3, 239–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, A., & Malouf, M. W. K. (1979). Game theoretic models and the role of information in bargaining. Psychological Review, 86, 574–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Siegel, S., & Fouraker, L. E. (1960). Bargaining and group decision making: Experiments in bilateral monopoly. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1996). Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1986). The economics of rights, cooperation, and welfare. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trockel, W. (2000). Implementations of the Nash solution based on its Walrasian characterization. Economic Theory, 16, 277–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Huyck, J., Battalio, R., Mathur, S., & Van Huyck, P. (1995). On the origin of convention: Evidence from symmetric bargaining games. International Journal of Game Theory, 24, 187–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, P. H. (1993). An evolutionary model of bargaining. Journal of Economic Theory, 59, 145–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version. We would also like to thank Arno Riedl for helpful comments. All remaining errors are ours.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emin Karagözoğlu.

Appendix

Appendix

In this appendix, we provide an extension of our mechanism to \(n>2\) players. First, we introduce some new notation. \(i=1,...,n\) still denotes players. If \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}\le 1\), then the game ends in the first stage and for all \(i, \pi _{i}=d_{i}\). If \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}>1\), then the game reaches the second stage and the player with the minimal first-stage demand is chosen to be the proposer in the ultimatum game. If \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}>1\) and there are multiple players with the common minimal first-stage demand, then each such player is chosen to be the proposer with equal probability. We assume that players are risk-neutral. We denote the excess by \(x\equiv \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}-1\). If player \(j\) is the proposer (i.e., either \(d_{j}\) is the unique minimal demand or player \(j\) is chosen among players with the minimal demand as a result of a random draw), to avoid \(x\) he makes a proposal \((x_{1},...,x_{n})\) to other players such that \( \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}x_{i}=x\). Each other player can either accept or reject this proposal. The proposer’s action set in the second stage is for every \(i, x_{i}\in [0,d_{i}]\) and the responders’ action sets in the second stage are \(\{accept,reject\}\). Footnote 12 If each responder accepts the proposal, then for all \(i, \pi _{i}=d_{i}-x_{i}\). If at least one responder rejects the proposal, then \(\pi _{1}=...=\pi _{n}=0\). Therefore, the mechanism requires a unanimous agreement. For clarification, below we provide some examples on how our mechanism works.

Example 1

Let \(n=5\) and \((d_{1},d_{2},d_{3},d_{4},d_{5})=(0.2,0.3,0.4,0.8,0.9)\). In this case, \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}>1, x =1.6\) and the minimal demand is unique. Player 1 proposes a split of \(x\). A possible allocation would be \((x_{1},x_{2},x_{3},x_{4},x_{5})=(0,0,0,0.7,0.9)\). This proposal would be accepted by all responding players and thus, for all \( i=1,2,3, \pi _{i}=d_{i}; \pi _{4}=0.1\), and \(\pi _{5}=0\).

Example 2

Let \(n\!=\!4\) and \((d_{1},d_{2},d_{3},d_{4})\!=\!(0.3,0.3,0.6,0.7)\). In this case, \( \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}>1, x =0.9\) and the minimal demand is not unique. A random draw determines the proposer. Without loss of generality, assume that player 2 is chosen to be the proposer. A possible allocation would be \((x_{1},x_{2},x_{3},x_{4})=(0,0,0.4,0.5)\). This proposal would be accepted by all responding players and thus, for all \( i=1,2, \pi _{i}=d_{i}\); \(\pi _{3}=0.2\), and \(\pi _{4}=0.2\).

Note that the proposals in these examples are just given for clarification purposes and hence may not be optimal in the subgame perfect sense. Characteristics of sequentially rational ultimatum proposals will be provided in the following proof.

Theorem 3

There exists payoff-equivalent multiple subgame perfect Nash equilibria of \(DD^{\prime }\) and \((d_{1},...,d_{n})=(1/n,...,1/n)\) in all equilibria.

Proof

We first show that the subgame perfect Nash equilibrium play induces \(x=0\) and there are multiple ways to avoid the excess in the second stage if it is reached (Claim 1). Then, we show that in subgame perfect Nash equilibrium, the minimal demand is equal to the maximal demand in the first stage (Claim 2). The result directly follows from these arguments.

Claim 1 Subgame perfect Nash equilibrium play induces \( x=0\).

The following exhaustive set of cases needs to be analyzed. In each case, we show that at least one profitable unilateral deviation exists.

Case 1 \(x<0\). Without loss of generality take player \(j\). Clearly, a unilateral deviation \(d_{j}^{\prime }=1-\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\ne j}d_{i}\) brings \(\pi ^{\prime }=1-\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\ne j}d_{i}>d_{j}=\pi _{j}\).

Case 2 \(x>0\). There are two subcases here. Before analyzing these subcases let us first take a look at the second-stage behavior. If and when the second stage of the game is reached, without loss of generality assume that player \(j\) is the proposer. As in Brams and Taylor (1994), we employ iterated elimination of weakly dominated strategies here.

For any responding player \(k\), playing accept brings \(\pi _{k}\in [0,d_{k}]\) and hence it weakly dominates (also there exist cases in which strict dominance occurs) playing reject. Thus, responding players choose to accept any proposal. This establishes the second-stage behavior of responding players.

Now, let us denote the set of players with the common maximal first-stage demand as \(H\) and the common value of the maximal demand as \( h\equiv \max \{d_{1},...,d_{n}\}\). Given that any responding player chooses to accept any proposal,there are two cases to be studied: if \(x\geqslant \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\in H}d_{i}\), then “offering \(x_{i}=d_{i}\) to all players in \(H\) and distributing the remaining amount \(x-\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon H}d_{i}\) to \(n-1-\left| H\right| \) players in such a way that for all remaining players, \(\pi _{i}\ge 0\)” weakly dominates all other strategies. Note that there are (infinitely) many ways of distributing \(x-\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon H}d_{i}\) to \(n-1-\left| H\right| \) players, which is why there exists multiple equilibria. On the other hand, if \(x< \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i \epsilon H}d_{i}\) then player \(j\) distributes \(x\) among the players in \(H\). In these two cases, weak domination follows from the fact that playing such, player \(j\) can always gurantee \(\pi _{j}=d_{j}\). This establishes the proposers’ second-stage behavior.

Case 2.1 Minimal demand is unique. Without loss of generality, assume that \(d_{j}=\min \{d_{1},...,d_{n}\}\). Denote the set of the remaining demands as \(A\), where \(A\equiv \{d_{i}\!\!:d_{i}\ne d_{j}\}\). Clearly, for player \(j\), a unilateral deviation \(d_{j}^{\prime }=\min (A)-\epsilon \) brings \(\pi _{j}^{\prime }=\min (A)-\epsilon >d_{j}=\pi _{j}\).

Case 2.2 Minimal demand is not unique. This means that there exists a set of players with the common minimal demand. Denote this set as \(M\) and the common value of the minimal demand as \(m\equiv \min \{d_{1},...,d_{n}\}\). There are two subcases.

Case 2.2.1 \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon M}d_{i}<1\). Then there are two subcases.

Case 2.2.1.1 \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon H}d_{i}\leqslant x \). Without loss of generality, take player \(j\in H\). Then for player \(j\), a unilateral deviation, \(d_{j}^{\prime }=m-\epsilon \) brings \(\pi _{j}^{\prime }=d_{j}^{\prime }=m-\epsilon >\pi _{j}=\epsilon \).

Case 2.2.1.2 \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon H}d_{i}>x\). Without loss of generality, take player \(j\in M\). Let \(d_{j}^{\prime \prime } \) be the demand that satisfies \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon H}d_{i}=x.\) Then, for player \(j\) a unilateral deviation, \(d_{j}^{\prime }=\min (h-\epsilon , d_{j}^{\prime \prime })\) brings \(\pi _{j}^{\prime }=d_{j}^{\prime }>\pi _{j}=d_{j}\).

Case 2.2.2 \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon M}d_{i}\geqslant 1\). This implies \(x\geqslant \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\epsilon H}d_{i}\). Without loss of generality, assume that player \(j\) is the one with the maximal demand. Thus, a unilateral deviation, \(d_{j}^{\prime }=m-\epsilon \) brings \(\pi _{j}^{\prime }=d_{j}^{\prime }=m-\epsilon >\pi _{j}=\epsilon .\)

Arguments above imply that in the subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium \(x=0\).

Claim 2 In the subgame perfect Nash equilbrium, \(x=0\) induces \(h=m\).

Case 1 \(h<m\). This case is impossible by definition.

Case 2 \(h>m\). Without loss generality player \(j\) is the one with the minimal first-stage demand. Therefore, a unilateral deviation to \(d_{j}^{\prime }=h-\epsilon \) brings \(\pi _{j}^{\prime }=h-\epsilon >\pi _{j}=d_{j}\). \(\square \)

The following theorem is a generalization of Theorem 2.

Theorem 4

There is no subgame perfect Nash equilibrium of \(DD^{\prime }\) (with \(n>2\)), which involves mixing in the first stage.

Proof

We will prove this result in steps.

Step 1 Claiming \(d_{i}<1/n\) is strictly dominated by claiming \(d_{i}=1/n\) , for every player \(i=1,2,...n\). Without loss of generality, let us focus on player \( 1 \). It is sufficient to investigate the following two cases \(x\le 0\) and \(x>0\).

Case 1 \(x\le 0\). Let us analyze a deviation from \( d_{1}<1/n\) to \(d_{1}^{\prime }=1/n\). Note here, we assume that (as in Theorem 3) in case the second stage is reached, the proposer will distribute \(x\) as follows: (i) he starts from \(h\) and if possible deducts the whole \(x\) from \(h\), if not possibe deducts as much as possible from \(h\); (ii) then he moves to the agent with the second highest demand follows the procedure in (i); and (iii) continues in the same fashion until \(x\) vanishes. Under this assumption, a deviation from \(d_{1}<1/n\) to \(d_{1}^{\prime }=1/n\) is always profitable for player \( 1 \). Note that, even if this deviation creates an excess, \(x>0\), it brings \(\pi _{1}^{\prime }=d_{1}^{\prime }>\pi _{1}\). To see why, observe that \(h>d_{1}^{\prime }\) and \(x<h\).

Case 2 \(x>0\). In this case, since \(x>0\) there must exist a player \(j\) with \(d_{j}>1/n\). Now, consider a deviation from \(d_{1}<1/n\) to \(d_{1}^{\prime }=1/n\). Clearly, \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i\in b}d_{i}<1\) where \(b \equiv \{i:d_{i}\le 1/n\}\). Therefore, under the assumption made in Case 1, \(x\) will vanish before reaching player \( 1 \). This implies that \(\pi _{1}^{\prime }=d_{1}^{\prime }>\pi _{1}\). Since player \( 1 \) was chosen without loss of generality, the result is valid for any player.

Step 2 In any subgame perfect equilibrium \(E(\pi _{i})\ge 1/n\), for every player \(i=1,2,...,n\).

From Step 1, we know that for any \(i\) setting \(d_{i}=1/n\) guarantees \(\pi _{i}=1/n\) independent of what other players do. Therefore, in any subgame perfect Nash Equilibrium of \(DD^{\prime }\), the expected payoff of any player should be greater or equal to \(1/n\).

Step 3 Subgame perfection implies \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}\pi _{i}=1\).

Suppose that, \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}>1\) and without loss of generality player \( 1 \) is the proposer in the second stage. Observe that there is always a way to divide \(x\) such that player \( 1 \) is not punished: by definition \(x=\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n}d_{i}-1\) and\(\ d_{1}\le 1\); therefore, \(x\le \mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{j\ne 1}d_{j}\). This implies, player \( 1 \) have uncountably many ways to divide the \(x\) to other players. Then, in any subgame perfect equilibrium \(\mathop {\textstyle \sum }\nolimits _{i=1}^{n} \pi _{i}=1\).

Therefore, combining Steps 1, 2, and 3 implies that in any subgame perfect equilibrium, \(E\left[ \pi _{1}\right] =...=E\left[ \pi _{n}\right] =1/n\).

Note that this equal division outcome, in principle, can be reached in different ways. For instance, all players may mix uniformly over \([1/n,1]\) Footnote 13, or one player may (purely) demand \(1/n\) and the others mix between \((1/n,1]\), or yet some of the players (purely) demand \(1/n\) and others mix over different demands. Nevertheless, Step 4 shows that this cannot be the case in equilibrium.

Step 4 Suppose without loss generality that players \( 2,...,N \) mix over \([1/n,1]\) using a probability distribution \(F\). First, we show that \(F\) cannot have atoms above \(1/n\). Suppose for a contradiction that it has an atom above \(1/n\). Hence, we can pick an arbitrary point \(a\) such that \(a>1/n\) and \(P(a)>0\). Now, suppose player \( 1 \) mixes using a distribution \(G\), which has a support \([1/n,a)\), which is first-order stochastically dominated by \(F\) and \(G(1/n)\ne 1\). As a result, we have \(E(\pi _{1})>E(\pi _{2})=...=E(\pi _{n})\) and hence \( E(\pi _{1})>1/n\) (a contradiction to \(E(\pi _{1})=E(\pi _{2})=...=E(\pi _{n})=1/n\)), where the second inequality follows from subgame perfection. This shows that \(F\) cannot have atoms above \(1/2\). In other words, we should not worry about ties in demands.

Suppose \(k<n\) players mix over demands within the support, \([1/n,1]\). For simplicity, assume that they use the same distribution, \(F\), which has a density above \(1/n\). \(\mathcal F \) denotes the joint distribution of demands for \(k\) players. Therefore, for player \(i\) playing \(d_{i}>1/n\) will bring an expected payoff , \(\pi _{i}(d_{i})\),

$$\begin{aligned} \pi _{i}(d_{i})&= (1-F(d_{i}))^{k}d_{i}+\mathop {\displaystyle \sum }_{h=1}^{k}\left( {\begin{array}{c}k\\ h\end{array}}\right) (1-F(d_{i}))^{h}\mathop {\displaystyle \idotsint }_{1/n}^{d_{i}}[\mathbf I _{\{\varphi >x\}}d_{i} \\&+((1-\mathbf I _{\{\varphi >x\}})\max (0,d_{i}-x+\varphi ))]f(d_{1})...f(d_{h})\mathbf d (d_{1})...\mathbf d (d_{h}) \\&+\max \left( 0,\mathop {\displaystyle \idotsint }_{1/n}^{d_{i}}(d_{i}-x)f(d_{1})...f(d_{n})\mathbf d (d_{1})....\mathbf d (d_{n})\right) , \end{aligned}$$

where \(\varphi \equiv \sum _{j\in L}d_{j}, L \equiv \{j:d_{j}>d_{i}\}\), is the set of agents with demands higher than \(d_{i}\) and \(\mathbf I _{\{\varphi >x\}}\) is the indicator function, which takes the value \(1\) if the sum of demands higher than \(d_{i}\) is less than \(x\) and \(0\) otherwise.Footnote 14

Observe that if we take the derivative of \(\pi _{i}(d_{i})\) with respect to \( d_{i}\), we get \(\pi _{i}^{\prime }(d_{i})=(1-F(d_{i}))^{k-1}-f(d_{i})\Phi +(1-F(d_{i}))\Psi +\mathop {\textstyle \sum }_{i=1}^{k}\gamma _{i}f(d_{i})(1-F(d_{i}))^{k}\) , where \(\Phi \),\(\Psi \), and \(\gamma \) are some positive constants. Obviously, if \(F(d_{i})<1\), this derivative is greater than zero. This implies that player \(i\) can receive a share higher than \(1/n\) just by marginally increasing his demand. This means that there must exist some player \(j\) with \(\pi _{j}<1/n\), which is in contradiction with findings from Steps 1, 2, and 3. Hence, a positive probability cannot be assigned to any demand above \(1/n\) in equilibrium.

Therefore, the result follows from Steps 1, 2, 3, and 4. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cetemen, E.D., Karagözoğlu, E. Implementing equal division with an ultimatum threat. Theory Decis 77, 223–236 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-013-9394-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-013-9394-z

Keywords

Navigation