Skip to main content
Log in

A parsimonious model of subjective life expectancy

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

On average, “young” people underestimate whereas “old” people overestimate their chances to survive into the future. Such subjective survival beliefs violate the rational expectations paradigm and are also not in line with models of rational Bayesian learning. In order to explain these empirical patterns in a parsimonious manner, we assume that self-reported beliefs express likelihood insensitivity and can, therefore, be modeled as non-additive beliefs. In a next step we introduce a closed form model of Bayesian learning for non-additive beliefs which combines rational learning with psychological attitudes in the interpretation of information. Our model gives a remarkable fit to average subjective survival beliefs reported in the Health and Retirement Study.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Our findings confirm results documented in a vast literature on subjective survival probabilities, see below.

  2. For women we do not observe such a clear convergent pattern even for this age group.

  3. That is, the prior and the posterior are conjugate distributions because both belong to the Beta distribution family.

  4. Tonks (1983) introduces a similar model of rational Bayesian learning in which the agent has a normally distributed prior over the mean of a normal distribution and receives normally distributed information.

  5. Besides the formal description of insensitivity to changes in likelihood (Wakker 2004), properties of non-additive beliefs are used in the literature for formal definitions of, e.g., ambiguity and uncertainty attitudes (Schmeidler 1989; Epstein 1999; Ghirardato and Marinacci 2002), as well as pessimism and optimism (Eichberger and Kelsey 1999; Wakker 2001; Chateauneuf et al. 2007). See Wakker (2010) for a textbook treatment.

  6. An axiomatic foundation under the assumption of CEU preferences is provided in Eichberger et al. (2007, 2010).

  7. Sensitivity analysis with respect to this assumption is presented in the online appendix.

  8. Results are available upon request.

  9. A qualitative difference is that inverse u-shaped experience translates into inverse u-shaped likelihood sensitivity.

  10. We owe this interpretation to an anonymous referee.

  11. In particular, it is not the purpose of this paper to analyze how updating of beliefs differs across particular idiosyncratic health shocks or other events that are regarded as relevant for survival belief formation in the literature, such as parental death. As we further discuss in our concluding remarks in Sect. 5, a more in depth analysis of survival belief formation based on idiosyncratic events using our framework is left for future research.

  12. Observe that this weighting scheme implies that our point estimates are identical to a regression based on average survival rates of each group. Parameter estimates from an un-weighted regression are similar and are available upon request.

  13. The value of the two-sided \(t\) test on the difference between the \(R^{2}\)s for men and women is 108.96 with a \(p\) value of 0.0. The values of Jarque-Bera test statistics for normality of the distribution of the bootstrapped \(R^{2}\)s (and their \(p\) values) are at 0.02 (0.99) for men and at 4.49 (0.10) for women so that a standard \(t\) test is applicable.

    Fig. 3
    figure 3

    Actual and predicted survival probabilities for psychologically biased Bayesian learning. Source Own calculations based on HRS, HMD, and SSA data

  14. The \(t\) statistic of the two-sided \(t\) test for equality of the point estimates is \(3.53\).

  15. In this argument, we can ignore for age 80 households the difference between the additive objective measure \(\pi \) and the additive subjective measure \( \tilde{b}\) because the bias factor \(\frac{2\phi ^{m-j}+h}{2+h}\) is close to one for that amount of experience.

    Fig. 5
    figure 5

    Probability weighting functions. Source Own calculations based on HRS, HMD, and SSA data

  16. An alternative interpretation is that focal point answers reflect ambiguity, cf. Hill et al. (2004).

  17. As Mike Hurd pointed out to us, the first selection effect was particularly severe for the early waves of the HRS because people were not followed into nursing homes in the past. Since we use the more recent waves of the HRS where people are in fact followed into nursing homes, selection effects may only play a role for the very old respondents in our sample, if at all.

References

  • Baron, J. (2008). Thinking and deciding. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., & Eeckhoudt, L. (2006). Survival risks, intertemporal consumption, and insurance: The case of distorted probabilities. Insurance Mathematics and Economics, 38, 335–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breiman, D., LeCam, L., & Schwartz, L. (1964). Consistent estimates and zero-one sets. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 35, 157–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruine de Bruin, W., Fischhoff, B., & Halpern-Felsher, S. (2000). Expressing epistemic uncertainty: It’s a fifty-fifty chance. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 81, 115–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, A., Eichberger, J., & Grant, S. (2007). Choice under uncertainty with the best and worst in mind: Neo-additive capacities. Journal of Economic Theory, 127, 538–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doob, J. L. (1949). Application of the theory of martingales. Le Calcul des Probabilités et ses Applications, Colloques Internationaux du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, 13, 23–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., Grant, S., & Kelsey, D. (2007). Updating choquet beliefs. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 43(7–8), 888–899.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., Grant, S., & Kelsey, D. (2010). Comparing three ways to update choquet beliefs. Economics Letters, 107(2), 91–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichberger, J., & Kelsey, D. (1999). {E-}Capacities and the Ellsberg Paradox. Theory and Decision, 46, 107–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. G. (1999). A definition of uncertainty aversion. Review of Economic Studies, 66, 579–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gan, L., Hurd, M., & McFadden, D. (2005). Individual subjective survival curves. In D. Wise (Ed.), Analyses in the economics of aging. Cambridge: NBER Books, National Bureau of Economic Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., & Marinacci, M. (2002). Ambiguity made precise: A comparative foundation. Journal of Economic Theory, 102, 251–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I. (1987). Expected utility with purely subjective non-additive probabilities. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 16, 65–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1993). Updating ambiguous beliefs. Journal of Economic Theory, 59, 33–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammermesh, D. S. (1985). Expectations, life expectancy, and economic behavior. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 100(2), 389–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, D., Perry, M., & Willis R. (2004). Estimating Knightian Uncertainty from Survival Probability Questions on the HRS. Presented at labor and social interaction in economics, A conference in honor of Yoram Weiss’ sixty-fifth birthday, The Eitan Berglas School of Economics, Tel-Aviv University, December 16–17.

  • Human Mortality Database (2008).

  • Hurd, M. D., McFadden, D., & Merrill, A. (2001). Predictors of mortality among the elderly. In D. Wise (Ed.), Themes in the economics of aging. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, M. D., & McGarry, K. (1995). Evaluation of the subjective probabilities of survival in the health and retirement study. Journal of Human Resources, 30(0), S268–S292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, M. D., & McGarry, K. (2002). The predictive validity of subjective probabilities of survival. Economic Journal, 112, 966–985.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, M. D., Rohwedder, S., & Winter, J. (2005). Subjective Probabilities of Survival: An International Comparison. Presented at CeMMAP workshop on Novel measurement methods for understanding economic behaviour, IFS, London, 3 July, 2008.

  • Kastenbaum, R. (2000). The psychology of death. New York: Springer Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khwaja, A., Sloan, F., & Chung, S. (2007). The relationship between individual expectations and behaviors: Evidence on mortality expectations and smoking decisions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 35(2), 179–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, R. D., & Carter, L. (1992). Modeling and forecasting U.S. mortality. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 87(419), 659–671.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lijoi, A., Pruenster, I., & Walker, S. O. (2004). Extending Doob’s consistency theorem to nonparametric densities. Bernoulli, 10, 651–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manski, C. F. (2004). Measuring expectations. Econometrica, 72(5), 1329–1376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McFadden, D. L., Bemmaor, A. C., Francis, G. C., Dominitz, J., Byung-Hill, J., Lewbel, A., et al. (2005). Statistical analysis of choice experiments and surveys. Marketing Letters, 16(3–4), 183–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pires, C. P. (2002). A rule for updating ambiguous beliefs. Theory and Decision, 53, 137–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarin, R., & Wakker, P. P. (1998). Revealed likelihood and knightian uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 16, 223–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1986). Integral representation without additivity. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 97, 255–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siniscalchi, M. (2011). Dynamic Choice under Ambiguity. Theoretical Economics, 6, 379–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V. K., Taylor, D. H., & Sloan, F. A. (2001). Longevity expectations and death: Can people predict their own demise? American Economic Review, 91(4), 1126–1134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V. K., Taylor, D. H., Sloan, F. A., Johnson, F. R., & Desvouges, W. H. (2001). Do Smokers Respond to Health Shocks? The Review of Economics and Statistics, 83(4), 675–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steffen, B. (2009). Formation and Updating of Subjective Life Expectancy. MEA Studies 08, MEA, LMU Munich.

  • Tonks, I. (1983). Bayesian Learning and the Optimal Investment Decision of the Firm. The Economic Journal, 93, 87–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representations of Uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K. (1985). A Bayesian Perspective on Biases in Risk Perception. Economics Letters, 17, 59–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K. (1990). Do smokers underestimate risks? Journal of Political Economy, 98(6), 1253–1269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K. (1991). Age variations in risk perceptions and smoking decisions. Review of Economics and Statistics, 73(4), 577–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K., & O’Connor, C. J. (1984). Adaptive responses to chemical labeling: Are workers Bayesian decision makers? Amercian Economic Review, 74, 942–956.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. (2001). Testing and characterizing properties of nonadditive measures through violations of the sure-thing principle. Econometrica, 69, 1039–1059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. (2004). On the composition of risk preference and belief. Psychological Review, 111, 236–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (2010). Prospect theory: For risk and ambiguity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, G., & Gonzalez, R. (1996). Curvature of the probability weighting function. Management Science, 42(12), 1676–1690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimper, A. (2009). Half empty, half full and why we can agree to disagree forever. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 71, 283–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimper, A., & Ludwig, A. (2009). On attitude polarization under Bayesian learning with non-additive beliefs. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39, 181–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Axel Börsch-Supan, Andrew Caplin, Alain Chateauneuf, Itzhak Gilboa, Mike Hurd, David Levine, Jürgen Maurer, Dan McFadden, Klaus Ritzberger, Susan Rohwedder, Aylit Romm, Martin Salm, Frank Sloan, Carsten Trenkler, Peter Wakker, David Weir, Joachim Winter, and an anonymous referee as well as several seminar participants at the Workshop on Subjective Probabilities and Expectations, Jackson Hole, Wyoming, 2007, at Universität Mannheim and the 2009 SAET Conference for helpful comments; and Frank Schilbach for his excellent research assistance. Financial support by the Social Security Administration (SSA) under the 2007 Steven H. Sandell Grant Program is gratefully acknowledged. Alex Ludwig further gratefully acknowledges financial support from the German National Research Foundation (DFG) through SFB 504, the State of Baden-Württemberg and the German Insurers Association (GDV). Alex Zimper is grateful for financial support from Economic Research Southern Africa (ERSA).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to A. Ludwig.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (pdf 136 KB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ludwig, A., Zimper, A. A parsimonious model of subjective life expectancy. Theory Decis 75, 519–541 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-013-9355-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-013-9355-6

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation