Skip to main content
Log in

Relativistic frameworks and the case for (or against) incommensurability

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to address, from a fresh perspective, the question of whether Newtonian mechanics can legitimately be regarded as a limiting case of the special theory of relativity (STR), or whether the two theories should be deemed so radically different as to be incommensurable in the sense of Feyerabend and Kuhn. Firstly, it is argued that focusing on the concept of mass and its transformation across the two varieties of mechanics is bound to leave the issue unsettled. On the one hand, the idea of a speed-dependent ‘relativistic mass’, which has been invoked in support of incommensurability claims, results from a particular, often innocuous but unnecessary and inappropriate reading of certain basic formulae. On the other hand, the existence of an invariant rest mass in STR does not warrant its identification with the Newtonian mass, be it in a suitable limit. This invariant notwithstanding, those who follow Feyerabend and Kuhn can still uphold their views with regard to the two theories. It is shown, however, that the two mechanics embody relativistic frameworks that are direct consequences of the same set of assumptions. As a result, if Newton’s mechanics cannot simply be regarded as a limiting case of STR, the possibility of ‘recovering’ from the latter some elements of the former can be traced to a common source, belying claims of logical disconnection between the two theories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Feynman’s emphasis on m as a non-classical notion of mass also appears to be at odds with his diagrammatic method for the calculation of terms in QED, since that method hinges on the concept of a Lorentz-invariant mass, i.e., on \(m_0 \), rather than any frame-dependent mass.

  2. For the sake of consistency, the symbols m and \(m_0\) have been substituted in the quoted passage wherever Einstein uses M and m. Notational ambiguity is pervasive in this matter and a hindrance to clarification.

  3. Inertia only reduces to mass (\(m_{0 } )\) in the rest frame of the body, i.e as \(p=0\) in the fundamental relation \(E^{2}=p^{2}c^{2}+m_{0} ^{2}c^{4}\). The case of light is special in that \(E=pc\) : there is no such rest frame and \(m_0 =0)\). Einstein (1935) includes rare emphasis on the energy-mass relation being \(E_0 =m_0 c^{2}\), where \(E_0 \) is the rest energy, and not \(E=mc^{2}\), where \(m=\gamma m_0 \). In contrast, Bergmann’s (1942) book, endorsed by Einstein, makes explicit reference to ‘relativistic mass’ (besides ‘rest mass’), but without discussing its physical significance.

  4. See e.g., Sandin (1991) for a rare defence, in recent years, of \(\gamma m_0 \) as the proper concept of mass in STR.

  5. Flores (2005), who discusses various positions regarding the significance of mass-energy equivalence and the idea of conversion between one and the other, appears to regard \(E=mc^{2}\) as a correct expression of such equivalence.

  6. As emphasized e.g., by Torretti (1990, Sect. 2.6.5).

  7. Excluding photons, for which there is no rest frame and correspondingly no PIM (see footnote 3).

  8. Besides early attempts by von Von Ignatowsky (1910), and Frank and Rothe (1911), significant—and much later—contributions include Lee and Kalotas (1975), Lévy-Leblond (1976), Mermin (1984) and Feigenbaum (2008).

  9. Uniform translational (rectilinear) motion means that, given a uniform method for measuring time and uniformly laid out spatial markers, distance covered is proportional to the time of coverage.

  10. Homogeneity should not be regarded as reflecting intrinsic properties of space or time, but as a sensible and convenient demand made on certain transformations. Thus, in the theory of system processing and control, homogeneity comes down to the requirement that a change in the amplitude of the input signal should give rise to a proportional change in the output signal’s amplitude. The resulting transformation is linear.

  11. The above-sketched derivation, like those footnote 8 refers to, hinges on the convenient reduction to 1 of the number of relevant spatial dimensions. As Feigenbaum (2008) points out, this oversimplifies the matter by reducing isotropy to parity. However, the outcome of Feigenbaum’s three-dimensional treatment mainly differs from more ‘pedestrian’ approaches in that isotropy and homogeneity (or rather UTUM) jointly suffice to determine a group law, which does not need to be assumed from the outset. If the Lorentz-Einstein transformation is identical with \(T_{R\rightarrow R^{\prime }} \) upon identification of \(\kappa \) with c, this is essentially because, since speed is a scalar, basing a RF on the constancy of the speed (not the velocity) of anything, be it light, implicitly assumes rotational invariance. This assumption goes a long way towards determining the form of the transformation. Isotropy is not enough, however, to uniquely select the Lorentz group (rather than the conformal group). Non-linearity, in particular, remains possible unless the homogeneity/UTUM assumption is brought in.

  12. The limitations of this approach are those of any mathematical idealization. We do not live in a frictionless and gravity-free world—if there could be such a world. Uniform rectilinear motion is an abstraction, and so are true inertial frames. However, Einstein’s ‘geometrodynamics’ (Misner et al. 1973)—which is not a more general theory of relativity—gives way to STR dynamics whenever curvature effects induced by gravity are deemed negligible, so that in effect the geometry becomes indistinguishable from that of Minkowski ‘flat’ spacetime.

References

  • Adler, C. G. (1987). Does mass really depend on velocity, dad? American Journal of Physics, 55(8), 739–743.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, P. G. (1942). Introduction to the theory of relativity. New York: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Born, M. (1962). Einstein’s theory of relativity. New York: Dover (First German edition: ‘Die Relativitätstheorie Einsteins und ihre physikalische Grundlagen gemeinverständlich dargestellt’. Berlin: Springer, 1920).

  • Einstein, A. (1905). Zur Elektrodynamik Bewegter Körper. Annalen der Physik, 17, 891–921.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1935). Elementary derivation of the equivalence of mass and energy. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 41, 223–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigenbaum, M. J. (2008). The theory of relativity—Galileo’s child. Retrieved Sept 1, 2016 from ArXiv e-print arXiv:0806.1234.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1962). Explanation, reduction and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time (Vol. 3, pp. 28–97). Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1981). Consolations for the specialist. In P. K. Feyerabend (Ed.), Problems of empiricism. philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 131–167). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1981b). Realism, rationalism and scientific method. Philosophical papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1987). Farewell to reason. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R., & Sands, M. (1965). The Feynman lectures on physics (Vol. 1). Reading MA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. P. (1998). Six not-so-easy pieces. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flores, F. (2005). Interpretations of Einstein’s equation \(E = mc^{2}\). International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 19(3), 245–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, P., & Rothe, H. (1911). Über die Transformationen der Raum-Zeitkoordinaten von ruhenden auf bewegte Systeme. Annalen der Physik, 34, 825–855.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (2000). Concepts of mass in contemporary physics and philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (enlarged 2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  • Lee, A. R., & Kalotas, T. M. (1975). Lorentz transformation from the first postulate. American Journal of Physics, 43, 434–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lévy-Leblond, J.-M. (1976). One more derivation of the Lorentz transformation. American Journal of Physics, 44, 271–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mermin, N. D. (1984). Relativity without Light. American Journal of Physics, 52, 119–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Misner, C. W., Thorne, K. S., & Wheeler, J. A. (1973). Gravitation. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okun, L. B. (1989). The concept of mass. Physics Today, 42(6), 31–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okun, L. B. (2008). The Einstein formula \(E_{0} = mc^{2}\). “Isn’t the Lord laughing?”. Physics–Uspekh, 51, 513–527. English translation, Retrieved from arXiv: 0808.0437.

  • Okun, L. B. (2009). Mass versus relativistic and rest masses. American Journal of Physics, 77(5), 430–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pauli, W. (1958). Theory of Relativity (First German ed. 1921). Oxford: Pergamon.

  • Post, H. R. (1971). Correspondence, invariance and heuristics. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 213–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rivadulla, A. (2004). The Newtonian limit of relativity theory and the rationality of theory change. Synthese, 141, 417–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandin, T. R. (1991). In defense of relativistic mass. American Journal of Physics, 59(11), 1032–1036.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torretti, R. (1990). Creative understanding. Philosophical reflections on physics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Von Ignatowsky, W. (1910). Einige allgemeine Bemerkungen zum Relativitätsprinzip. Physikalische Zeitschrift, 11, 972–976.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean-Michel Delhôtel.

Appendix: derivation of relativistic transformations

Appendix: derivation of relativistic transformations

Given two inertial frames \(R\equiv (O;x,y,z)\) and \(R^{\prime }\equiv (O^{\prime };x^{\prime }, y^{\prime },z^{\prime })\), we seek a general transformation \(T_{R\rightarrow {R}^{\prime }}\) such that the expression P(xyzt) of a physical quantity, relative to frame R, systematically transforms into \(Q\left( {x^{\prime },y^{\prime },z^{\prime },t^{\prime }} \right) \) relative to \(R^{\prime }\), where t and \(t^{\prime }\) refer to clock readings in R and \(R^{\prime }\) respectively. Isotropy warrants choosing the direction of the relative rectilinear uniform motion of R and \(R^{\prime }\) as that of an arbitrary axis (Ox) with respect to R, and that of (\(O^{\prime }x^{\prime })\) with respect to \(R^{\prime }\), such that (Ox) and (\(O^{\prime }x^{\prime })\) are parallel. Since directions orthogonal to (\(Ox)/(O^{\prime }x^{\prime })\) do not contribute anything nontrivial to the change-of-frame transformation \(T_{R\rightarrow {R}^{\prime }} \), and assuming that the origins and three pairs of parallel axes (\(Ox)/(O^{\prime }x^{\prime })\), (\(Oy)/(O^{\prime }y^{\prime })\) and (\(Oz)/(O^{\prime }z^{\prime })\) coincide when clocks \(C_{R}\) in R and \(C_{{R}^{\prime }}\) in \(R^{\prime }\) both read 0, then \(y=y^{\prime }\) and \(z=z^{\prime }\) for all readings of the two clocks. Deriving \(T_{R\rightarrow {R}^{\prime }}\) then reduces to working out f and g such that \(x^{\prime }=f\left( {x,t} \right) \) and \(t^{\prime }=g\left( {x,t} \right) \).

Spatial homogeneity requires that the difference \(f\left( {x_2 ,t} \right) -f\left( {x_1 ,t} \right) \) (‘rod length’ in the direction of motion) should not be affected by an arbitrary shift in the x coordinate i.e.

$$\begin{aligned} f\left( {x_2 +\varepsilon ,t} \right) -f\left( {x_1 +\varepsilon ,t} \right) =f\left( {x_2 ,t} \right) -f\left( {x_1 ,t} \right) . \end{aligned}$$

Dividing by \(\varepsilon \) and taking the \(\varepsilon \rightarrow 0\) limit, this condition amounts to \(\left. {\frac{\partial f}{\partial x}} \right| _{x_1 } =\left. {\frac{\partial f}{\partial x}} \right| _{x_2 } \): given the arbitrariness of \(x_1 \) and \(x_2 \), f is a linear function of x, and so is g. Similar considerations with respect to the endpoints of any time interval lead to the conclusion that f and g are linear functions of time. Alternatively, since \(dx^{\prime } = ~\frac{{\partial f}}{{\partial x}}dx + ~\frac{{\partial f}}{{\partial t}}dt\) and \(dt^{\prime } = ~\frac{{\partial g}}{{\partial x}}dx + ~\frac{{\partial g}}{{\partial t}}dt\) , that uniform motion in R appears as uniform in \(R^{\prime }\) (UTUM) requires all partial derivatives to be independent of x and t. \(T_{R\rightarrow {R}^{\prime }}\) thus takes the form \(\left\{ {{\begin{array}{l} {x^{\prime }=\gamma x+\delta t} \\ {t^{\prime }=\alpha x+\beta t} \\ \end{array} }} \right. \), where the coefficients \(\alpha , \beta \), \(\gamma \), \(\delta \) depend only on the relative velocity of the two frames.

As seen from R, the origin \(O^{\prime }\) of \(R^{\prime }\) (\(x^{\prime }=0)\) is such that \(\gamma x=-\delta t\): it is observed to be moving with the velocity \(v=-\frac{\delta }{\gamma }\). From the viewpoint of \(R^{\prime }\), the origin O of R (\(x=0)\) moves in the opposite direction with velocity \(-v=\frac{\delta }{\beta }\) . Therefore, \(\beta =\gamma \) and since \(\delta =-\gamma v\), this reduces the task to working out the form of two unknown coefficients  \(\alpha \) and \(\gamma \), functions of v only, such that \(T_v \equiv T_{R\rightarrow {R}^{\prime }} : \left\{ {{\begin{array}{l} {x^{\prime }=\gamma \left( v \right) x-\gamma \left( v \right) vt} \\ {t^{\prime }=\alpha \left( v \right) x+\gamma \left( v \right) t} \\ \end{array} }} \right. \).

\(T_v \) should be invariant under a reflection in the parallel planes \((yz)/(y'z')\). If \(\tilde{R}\) is the image of R under such reflection, and \(\tilde{R^{\prime }}\) that of \(R^{\prime }\), then \(\tilde{x} = -x, \widetilde{x^{\prime }} =-x^{\prime }, {\tilde{t}} =t, \tilde{t^{\prime }} =t^{\prime }\). As seen from \(\tilde{R}, \tilde{R^{\prime }}\) is in uniform rectilinear motion with velocity \(-v\) i.e. \(T_{\tilde{R}\rightarrow \tilde{R^{\prime }}}\, \equiv \, T_{-v} \) . It follows that \(\gamma \) is an even function of \(v: \gamma \left( {-v} \right) =\gamma \left( v \right) \), and that \(\alpha \) is odd: \(\alpha \left( {-v} \right) =-\alpha \left( v \right) \) (the same conclusions obtain upon considering time reversal instead of a mirror image).

A third inertial frame \(R^{{\prime }{\prime }}\) is introduced, which is in rectilinear uniform motion relative to \(R^{\prime }\), with velocity \(v^{\prime }\), in the (\(O^{{\prime }{\prime }}x^{{\prime }{\prime }})\) direction parallel to (Ox). A clock \(C_{{R}^{{\prime }{\prime }}}\) at rest in \(R^{{\prime }{\prime }}\) shows time \(t^{{\prime }{\prime }}\). The origins and axes of all three frames are most conveniently chosen so as to coincide when all of their respective clocks read 0. Requiring that \(T_{v^{\prime }} T_v =T_{v^{\prime \prime }} \), where \(v^{{\prime }{\prime }}\) is the velocity of \(R^{{\prime }{\prime }}\) relative to R, is equivalent to the set of simultaneous equations:

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ {\begin{array}{l} {\gamma ^{\prime }\left( {\gamma - \alpha v^{\prime }} \right) = \gamma ^{{\prime }{\prime }}\qquad \left( a \right) }\\ {\gamma \gamma ^{\prime }\left( {v + v^{\prime }} \right) = \gamma ^{{\prime }{\prime }}v^{{\prime }{\prime }}\qquad \left( b \right) }\\ {\alpha ^{\prime } \gamma + \alpha \gamma ^{\prime } = \alpha ^{{\prime }{\prime }}\qquad \left( c \right) }\\ {\gamma \left( {\gamma ^{\prime } - \alpha ^{\prime } v} \right) = \gamma ^{{\prime }{\prime }}\qquad \left( d \right) } \end{array}} \right. \end{aligned}$$

where \(\alpha ^{\prime }\equiv \alpha (v^{\prime }),\gamma ^{{\prime }{\prime }}\equiv \alpha \left( {{v}^{{\prime }{\prime }}} \right) )\) etc.

From \(\left( a \right) \) and \(\left( d \right) : \frac{\alpha ^{\prime }}{{{\gamma }^{{\prime }}{v^{\prime }}}}=\frac{\alpha }{\gamma v}\) and since \(\frac{\alpha }{\gamma v}\) depends on v only, and \(\frac{\alpha ^{\prime }}{{{\gamma }^{{\prime }}{v^{\prime }}}}\) on \(v^{\prime }\), equality implies that those ratios are independent of the relative velocity of the frames, hence equal to a ‘universal’ constant \(\lambda \). Given \(\alpha =\lambda \gamma v\), dividing \(\left( b \right) \) by \(\left( a \right) \) then yields the composition law for velocities: \(v^{{\prime }{\prime }}=\frac{v+v^{\prime }}{1-\lambda vv^{\prime }}\) .

From \(\left( a \right) \) with \({v}^{\prime }= -v\) and \(v^{{\prime }{\prime }}=0~: \gamma \left( v \right) \gamma \left( {-v} \right) =\frac{\gamma \left( 0 \right) }{1+\lambda v^{2}}\), and letting \(v=0\, (\gamma \ne 0)\) implies \(\gamma \left( 0 \right) =1\). Since \(\gamma \) is an even function of v, \(\gamma \left( v \right) \gamma \left( {-v} \right) =\gamma \left( v \right) ^{2}\), hence \(\gamma \left( v \right) =\frac{1}{\sqrt{1+\lambda v^{2}}}\) . This completes the derivation of \(T_v \) : \(\left\{ {{\begin{array}{l} {x^{\prime }=\frac{x-vt}{\sqrt{1+\lambda v^{2}}}} \\ {t^{\prime }=\frac{t+\lambda vx}{\sqrt{1+\lambda v^{2}}}} \\ \end{array} }} \right. \)

  • \(\lambda =0\) yields the Galilei transformation: \(\left\{ {{\begin{array}{l} {x^{\prime }=x-vt} \\ {t^{\prime }=t} \\ \end{array} }} \right. \).

  • If \(\lambda < 0\), then with \(\lambda =-\frac{1}{\kappa ^{2}}, T_{R\rightarrow {R}^{\prime }} \equiv T_{v,\kappa } :\left\{ {{\begin{array}{l} {x^{\prime }=\frac{x-vt}{\sqrt{1-\frac{v^{2}}{\kappa ^{2}}}}} \\ {t^{\prime }=\frac{t-\frac{v}{\kappa ^{2}}x}{\sqrt{1-\frac{v^{2}}{\kappa ^{2}}}}} \\ \end{array} }} \right. \),

which is such that \(x^{{\prime }{2}}-\kappa ^{2}t^{{\prime }{2}}=x^{2}-\kappa ^{2}t^{2}\), a non-Euclidean metric invariant that suggests formulating the (S)RF in terms of a four-dimensional space-time, in contrast with the ‘3+1’ formulation of Galilei-Newtonian mechanics. \(T_{v,c}\) is the Lorentz transformation given identification of \(\kappa \) with the speed of light c.

As developed in Sect. 3, dynamics in the \(\lambda < 0\) case is subject to an energy-momentum change-of-frame transformation, the form of which is a transposition of \(T_{v,\kappa } \):

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ {{\begin{array}{l} {p^{\prime }=\gamma \left( {p-\frac{v}{\kappa ^{2}}E} \right) } \\ {{E}^{\prime }}=\gamma (E-vp)\\ \end{array} }} \right. , \end{aligned}$$

The corresponding invariant \(E^{{\prime }2}-p^{{\prime }{2}}\kappa ^{2}=E^{2}-p^{2}\kappa ^{2}\) is \(E_0 ^{2}=\mu \kappa ^{2}\), where \(\mu \) can be interpreted as a Proper Inertial Mass (PIM) and \(E_0 \) is the total energy in the rest i.e. ‘zero-momentum’ frame of the object.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Delhôtel, JM. Relativistic frameworks and the case for (or against) incommensurability. Synthese 195, 1569–1585 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1283-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1283-x

Keywords

Navigation