Skip to main content
Log in

A frame-based approach for theoretical concepts

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to a seminal paper by Barsalou (Frames, fields, and contrasts, 1992), frames are attribute-value-matrices for representing exemplars or concepts. Frames have been used as a tool for reconstructing scientific concepts as well as conceptual change within scientific revolutions (Andersen and Nersessian, in Philos Sci 67:224–241, 2000; Chen and Barker, in Philos Sci 67:208–223, 2000; Chen, in Philos Sci 70:962–974, 2003; Barker et al., in Thomas Kuhn, 2003; Andersen et al., in The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions, 2006; Votsis and Schurz, in Stud Hist Philos Sci 43:105–114, 2012, in Concept types and frames. Application in language, cognition, and science, 2014). In the frame-based representations of scientific concepts developed so far the semantic content of concepts is (partially) determined by a set of attribute-specific values. This way of representing semantic content works best for prototype concepts and defined concepts of a conceptual taxonomy satisfying the no-overlap principle. In addition to the semantic content of prototype concepts and defined concepts, frames can also contain empirical knowledge that is represented as constraints between the values of the frame. Beside prototype concepts and defined concepts, theoretical concepts that are multiply operationalized play an important role in science. However, so far no frame-based representation of theoretical concepts has been proposed. In this paper, it will be shown that theoretical concepts can be represented by frames and that frame-based representations of prototype concepts and defined concepts have another structure than frame-based representations of theoretical concepts. In order to explicate this difference, we will develop a frame-based method for representing all three kinds of concepts by means of mathematical graph-theory. One important consequence will be that the constraints of a frame representing a theoretical concept are entailed by the structure of the frame, as opposed to a frame representing defined or prototype concepts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Beside the representation of prototype concepts, frames are often used to represent family resemblance concepts in order to reconstruct incommensurability and conceptual change in scientific revolutions (cf. Andersen et al. 1996, 2006; Chen et al. 1998). For the sake of brevity, we do not discuss the similarities and differences between prototype and family resemblance concepts and confine to the former.

  2. The prototypicality i.n.s. of a property corresponds to the notion of cue validity of Rosch et al. (1976, p. 384).

  3. Note that we presuppose a narrow view of definitions as conjunctions of properties. More complicated versions of definitions—for example, a disjunction of properties—will not be discussed in this article.

  4. In the following, we will always refer to standard English and standard Spanish. However, some of the examples that are unacceptable in standard English might be acceptable in some idiolects.

  5. The symbol “*” designates the unacceptability of the clause that follows the symbol.

  6. Since the publication of Chomsky and Lasnik (1977), constructions of this kind have usually been referred to as that-t filter violations. However, in this paper we use the original notion of Perlmutter (1971) that, in accordance with Gilligan (1987, p. 105), is assumed to address the same grammatical phenomena.

  7. Perlmutter (1971) is considered to be the first analysis that correlates the three grammatical phenomena SSE, NTS and NNTS and explains the typological differences with a single principle. Although Perlmutter (1971) did not call the explaining principle a parameter, in the generative literature he is considered to be one of the initiators of parameter research, especially of the research on the pro-drop parameter, since “the data Perlmutter noted is the first cross-linguistic generalization, i.e., parameter, in generative grammar. For better or worse, it has served as the basis for all subsequent work on Pro-drop phenomena” (Gilligan 1987, p. 76).

  8. For the following definitions, we refer to Hartsfield and Ringel (1990, Ch.1, Ch. 6.2 and Ch. 7.3).

  9. In the same way the frame of Fig. 2 is an OF(non-pro drop, language). Hence, the frame of Fig. 2 contains two operationalizing frames. For the sake of brevity, we only discuss the OF(pro drop, language).

  10. The notion of specialization originates in structuralism (also called non-statement view of theories), according to Sneed (1971), Stegmüller (1976, 1979), and Balzer et al. (1987) (for a short introduction see Moulines 2002; Andreas and Zenker 2014; Kornmesser 2008, 2014). The non-statement view of theories follows Suppes’ (1957) method of axiomatizing a theory by the definition of a set-theoretic predicate that contains the concepts and laws of the theory. A structure that satisfies the conditions of the predicate axiomatizing the theory is called a model of the theory. Hence, according to the non-statement view of theories, a theory T is represented extensionally as a set of models. A specialization \(\hbox {T}^{\prime }\) of a theory T is a strengthening of the logical content of T by adding further special laws to T (Balzer and Sneed 1977, pp. 201–202; Balzer et al. 1987, pp. 168–171). Therefore, the set of models satisfying \(\hbox {T}^{\prime }\) is a subset of the set of models satisfying T. Thus, the main idea of our notion of specialization remains the same as in structuralism, but is translated to a frame-based representation: The content of the operationalized concept is strengthened by adding further operationalizing conditions. Thus, the number of contraints entailed by the multiple operationalization increases (see below), and, from an extensional point of view, the number of entities in the extension of the operationalized concept decreases.

  11. Safir (1985) uses the terms NOM-drop Parameter and Free Inversion Parameter to designate the two parameters.

  12. Even every single axiom entails empirical content, since SSE, NTS, and NNTS are reconstructed as permanent dispositions. Hence, we get from one of the axioms, say Ax-1, the following empirical content: \(\forall \hbox {x}_1 ,\hbox {x}_2 ,\hbox {y}\left( {\hbox {L}\left( \hbox {y} \right) \wedge \hbox {NTS}\left( {\hbox {x}_1 ,\hbox {y}} \right) \wedge \hbox {NTS}\left( {\hbox {x}_2 ,\hbox {y}} \right) \rightarrow \left( {\hbox {G}\left( {\hbox {x}_1 ,\hbox {y}} \right) \leftrightarrow \hbox {G}\left( {\hbox {x}_2 ,\hbox {y}} \right) } \right) } \right) \).

  13. Beside the similarities to the linguistic representation of theories, we think that there are interesting parallels to the non-statement view of theories (see footnote 10). Elaborating on the relations between frame-based representations of theories and the more common methods of representing theories linguistically as sets of statements (Carnap) or as sets of models (Sneed, Stegmüller) is of great interest for the comparison of different methods of theory-representation as, for example, it is done by Zenker (2014) and Zenker and Gärdenfors (2014), who compare the representation of conceptual change in empirical science by frames, conceptual spaces, and sets of models.

References

  • Andersen, H., & Nersessian, N. J. (2000). Nomic concepts, frames, and conceptual change. Philosophy of Science, 67(Proceedings), 224–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H., Barker, P., Chen, X., et al. (1996). Kuhn’s mature philosophy of science and cognitive psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 9, 347–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H., Barker, P., Chen, X., et al. (2006). The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge: University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Andreas, H., & Zenker, F. (2014). Basic concepts of structuralism. Erkenntnis, 79, 1367–1372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., & Sneed, J. D. (1977). Generalized net structures of empirical theories, part I. Studia Logica, 36, 195–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., Moulines, C. U., & Sneed, J. D. (1987). An architectonic for science. The structuralist program. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, P., Chen, X., Andersen, H., et al. (2003). Kuhn on concepts and categorization. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Thomas Kuhn (pp. 212–245). Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1992). Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In A. Lehrer & E. F. Kittay (Eds.), Frames, fields, and contrasts (pp. 21–74). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W., & Hale, C. R. (1993). Components of conceptual representation: From feature lists to recursive frames. In I. Van Mechelen, J. Hampton, R. S. Michalski, & P. Theuns (Eds.), Categories and concepts: Theoretical views ans inductive data analysis (pp. 97–144). London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1936). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical terms. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1963). Carl G. Hempel on scientific theories. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 958–966). London: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X. (2003). Object and event concepts. A cognitive mechanism of incommensurability. Philosophy of Science, 70, 962–974.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X., & Barker, P. (2000). Continuity through revolutions: A frame-based account of conceptual change during scientific revolutions. Philosophy of Science, 67, 208–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X., Andersen, H., & Barker, P. (1998). Kuhn’s theory of scientific revolutions and cognitive psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 11, 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of language. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N., & Lasnik, H. (1977). Filters and control. Linguistic Inquiry, 8, 425–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, G. M. (1987). A cross-linguistic approach to the pro-drop parameter. University of California Ph. D. Dissertation.

  • Hartsfield, N., & Ringel, G. (1990). Pearls in graph theory. A comprehensive introduction. Boston: Academic Press Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, R. S. (1980). Extensions of binding and case-marking. Linguistic Inquiry, 11, 75–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornmesser, S. (2008). Theoretizität im Logischen Empirismus und im Strukturalismus – erläutert am Fallbeispiel des Neurobiologischen Konstruktivismus. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 39, 53–67.

  • Kornmesser, S. (2014). Model-based research programs. Conceptus, 41, 135–187.

  • Moulines, C. U. (2002). Introduction. Structuralism as a program for modelling theoretical science. In: Synthese (Vol. 130, pp. 1–11).

  • Perlmutter, D. M. (1971). Deep and surface structure constraints in syntax. New York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, W. (2007). Representation of concepts as frames. In J. Skilters, F. Toccafondi, & G. Stemberg (Eds.), Complex cognition and qualitative science. The baltic international yearbook of cognition, logic and communication (Vol. 2, pp. 151–170). Riga: University of Latvia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzi, L. (1982). Issues in Italian syntax. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., Mervis, C. B., Gray, W. D., Johnson, D. M., Boyes-Bream, P., et al. (1976). Basic objects in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8, 382–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Safir, K. J. (1985). Syntactic chains. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2008). Patterns of abduction. Synthese, 164, 201–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2012). prototypes and their composition from anevolutionary point of view. In M. Werning, W. Hinzen, & E. Machery (Eds.), The oxford handbook of compositionality (pp. 530–553). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2013). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2014). Criteria of Theoreticity: Bridging statement and non-statement view. Erkenntnis, 79, 1521–1545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J. D. (1971). The logical structure of mathematical physics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1970). Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und der Analytischen Philosophie. Band II. Theorie und Erfahrung. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1976). The structure and dynamics of theories. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1979). The structuralist view of theories. A possible analogue of the Bourbaki programme in physical science. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1957). Introduction to logic. New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Auwera, J. (1984). Subject vs. non-subject asymmetries in the relativization of embedded NP’s. In W. de Geest & Y. Putseys (Eds.), Sentential Complementation. Proceedings of the international conference held at UFSAL, Brussels, June 1983 (pp. 257–269). Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

  • Votsis, I., & Schurz, G. (2012). A frame-theoretic analysis of two rival conceptions of heat. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 43(1), 105–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Votsis, I., & Schurz, G. (2014). Reconstructing scientific theory change by means of frames. In T. Gamerschlag, D. Gerland, R. Osswald, & W. Petersen (Eds.), Concept types and frames. Application in language, cognition, and science (pp. 93–110). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zenker, F. (2014). From features via frames to spaces: Modeling scientific conceptual change without incommensurability or aprioricity. In T. Gamerschlag, D. Gerland, R. Osswald, & W. Petersen (Eds.), Concept types and frames. Application in language, cognition, and science (pp. 69–89). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zenker, F., & Gärdenfors, P. (2014). Modeling diachronic changes in structuralism and in conceptual spaces. Erkenntnis, 79, 1547–1561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For valuable comments I am indebted to Michael Schippers, Mark Siebel, and two anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephan Kornmesser.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kornmesser, S. A frame-based approach for theoretical concepts. Synthese 193, 145–166 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0750-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0750-0

Keywords

Navigation