Skip to main content
Log in

Remarks on counterpossibles

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Since the publication of David Lewis’ Counterfactuals, the standard line on subjunctive conditionals with impossible antecedents (or counterpossibles) has been that they are vacuously true. That is, a conditional of the form ‘If p were the case, q would be the case’ is trivially true whenever the antecedent, p, is impossible. The primary justification is that Lewis’ semantics best approximates the English subjunctive conditional, and that a vacuous treatment of counterpossibles is a consequence of that very elegant theory. Another justification derives from the classical lore than if an impossibility were true, then anything goes. In this paper we defend non-vacuism, the view that counterpossibles are sometimes non-vacuously true and sometimes non-vacuously false. We do so while retaining a Lewisian semantics, which is to say, the approach we favor does not require us to abandon classical logic or a similarity semantics. It does however require us to countenance impossible worlds. An impossible worlds treatment of counterpossibles is suggested (but not defended) by Lewis (Counterfactuals. Blackwell, Oxford, 1973), and developed by Nolan (Notre Dame J Formal Logic 38:325–527, 1997), Kment (Mind 115:261–310, 2006a: Philos Perspect 20:237–302, 2006b), and Vander Laan (In: Jackson F, Priest G (eds) Lewisian themes. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2004). We follow this tradition, and develop an account of comparative similarity for impossible worlds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Brogaard, B. (2007a). Comments on Delia Graff Fara’s coincidence by another name. Arizona Ontology Conference, Jan 2007. [http://brogaardb.googlepages.com/CommentsonDeliaGraffFara.doc].

  • Brogaard, B. (2008). Sea-battle semantics. Philosophical Quarterly 58(231), 326–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B., & Salerno, J. (2008). Counterfactuals and context. Analysis 68(1), 39–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.: The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1998). The tyranny of the subjunctive. [http://consc.net/papers/tyranny.htlm].

  • Chalmers D.: On sense and intension. Philosophical Perspectives 16, 135–182 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.: The foundations of two-dimensional semantics. In: Garcia-Carpintero, M., Macia, J. (eds) Two-dimensional semantics: Foundations and applications, pp. 55–139. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2011). Propositions and attitude ascriptions: A fregean account. Nous, 45, 595–639.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D., Jackson F.: Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review 110, 315–361 (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine K.: Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives 8, 1–16 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. Most counterfactuals are false, Manuscript.

  • Jackson F.: Conditionals. Blackwell, Oxford (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kallestrup, J. (2009). Conceivability, rigidity and counterpossibles. Synthese, 171(3), 377–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim S., Maslen C.: Counterfactuals as short stories. Philosophical Studies 129, 81–117 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kment B.: Counterfactuals and explanation. Mind 115, 261–310 (2006a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kment, B. (2006b). Counterfactuals and the analysis of necessity. Philosophical Perspectives, 20, 237–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S.: Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D.: Counterfactuals. Blackwell, Oxford (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and times arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.

  • Lewis, D. (1981). Ordering semantics and premise semantics for counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 10(2), 217–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D.: On the plurality of worlds. Basil Blackwell, Oxford (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. (1919). External and internal relations. Aristotelian Society.

  • Nolan D.: Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal for Formal Logic 38, 325–527 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G., & Routley, R. (1984). Introduction: Paraconsistent logics. Studia Logica, 43(1–2), 3–16.

  • Wierenga, E. (1998). Theism and counterpossibles. Philosophical studies, 89(1), 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vander Laan D.: Counterpossibles and similarity. In: Jackson, F., Priest, G. (eds) Lewisian themes, Oxford University Press, Oxford (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson B.: Indicatives and subjunctives. Philosophical Quarterly 51, 200–216 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The Philosophy of Philosophy, Blackwell.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Berit Brogaard.

Additional information

To appear in J. van Bentham, V. Hendricks, J. Symons, and S. A. Pedersen (eds.) Between Logic and Intuition: David Lewis and the Future of Formal Methods in Philosophy, Synthese Library, 2008.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Brogaard, B., Salerno, J. Remarks on counterpossibles. Synthese 190, 639–660 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0196-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0196-6

Keywords

Navigation