Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Educating moral emotions: a praxiological analysis

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents a praxiological analysis of three everyday educational practices or strategies that can be considered as being directed at the moral formation of the emotions. The first consists in requests to imagine other's emotional reactions. The second comprises requests to imitate normative emotional reactions and the third to re-appraise the features of a situation that are relevant to an emotional response. The interest of these categories is not just that they help to organize and recognize the significance of what might otherwise appear to be a disparate set of ordinary moral-educational interactions between children and educators. We suggest, further, that this analysis provides some new insight into what distinguishes the broad and recurrent conceptions of moral education from one another. Rather than being straightforwardly reducible to intractable differences over core normative or meta-ethical questions they can also be seen as correlating with different suppositions about the central role of the emotions in moral life and, correspondingly, different but to a large degree compatible interpretations of what the "education of the moral emotions" primarily means.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On the distinction between self- and other-focussed perspective taking see Hoffman (2000) and Blum (1980a, b).

  2. This is much of what lies behind the fact that rationalizations for failures to meet obligations to people in need often turn on claims about desert: the pittance paid out to recipients of social assistance is justified because such people are lazy (i.e., they could find work if they wanted to); provocative clothing worn by women who are victims of sexual harassment or assault should be considered a mitigating circumstance when assessing the degree of guilt of the male perpetrator, etc. For a general discussion of desert-based emotions see Kristjánsson (2003). On the relationship between sympathy and desert see the classic discussion in Smith (1790/1976).

  3. Nietzsche’s moral psychology represents a rare dissenting view. See, e.g., 2003 .

  4. De Sousa labels the latter “nasty” emotions and the former “nice” emotions (cf. 2001). For a similar account see Ben Ze’ev (2001).

  5. This is the subject of much philosophical controversy and to elaborate on these complex issues is not relevant to the present discussion. For the purposes of our argument, it is only important that some people actually hold that the construction of moral problems, etc. draws on capacities of empathic response and not whether or not this is the case.

  6. See Steutel and Spiecker (2004), pp. 542–543 for a detailed account of the operation of habituation.

  7. The assumption that feelings can be avoided by avoiding the situations that cause the feelings seems to underlie the legal measure known as a “restraining orders” where men found guilty of domestic violence are legally barred from entering the proximity of their former victims and diagnosed paedophiles may not go near schools.

  8. Other examples can be found in the teaching material comprising the well-received Second-Step anti-violence program.

  9. On this “cognitive” strategy of emotional regulation see Kristjánsson (2005), p. 687 and Ben Ze’ev (2000), pp. 229–233.

  10. Full rationality is understood in Bernard William’s (1981) broad sense of being based on no false beliefs, having only relevant true beliefs and correct deliberation.

  11. It is also undoubtedly true that Aristotle holds that even a central role of the virtue of phronesis, practical wisdom, is the moderation of unruly emotions by way of re-appraisal. Our point in associating re-appraisal with Kant and imitation with Aristotle is not meant to deny this. Indeed, the richness of Kant’s and Aristolte’s ethics is such we have no hesitation in postulating that one will find in both their work an acknowledgement of all three ways in which emotions have moral significance which we have identified—although differences will be apparent in the fined-grained interpretation of their significance. We claim that Kant’s ethics seems to have a greater affinity with re-appraisal, and Aristotle’s with imitation, mainly because of the centrality that each thinker seems to assign to the respective role of these strategies in the achievement of their respective moral ideals. Though the issues here are of a degree of complexity which resists simple formulation, Kant is wary of more-or-less mindless habituation because it is difficult to square with his ideal of rational autonomy. For his part, Aristotle, and on this point he contrasts sharply with Kant, generally regards the conformity of actions to one’s moral obligations willingly and, in some cases, frankly enjoying it a requirement of virtue. Habituation plays a crucial role in the achievement of this ideal because in many cases—the typical example is facing the enemy courageously in battle—the only way of getting there is by de-sensitising oneself (or, depending on the case, sensitising oneself) by way of repeated experiences where one tries to performing the virtuous act virtuously. Cf. Aristotle (1955), 1103a14ff.

References

  • Adalbjarnardóttir, S. (1993). Promoting children’s social growth in the schools: An intervention study. Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology, 14, 461–484

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958/1981). Modern moral philosophy. In The collected philosophical papers of G. E. M. Anscombe, Vol. 3, Ethics, religion and politics (pp. 26–42). Oxford: Basil Blackwell

  • Aristotle (4th century B.C.E./1955). Nicomachean ethics. J.A.K. Thomson (Trans.). London: Penguin

  • Bandura A. (1977). Self-efficacy: Toward a unifying theory of behavioral change. Psychological Review, 84(2), 191–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, M. W. (1997). Kantian ethics. In M. Baron, P. Pettit, & M. Slote (Eds.), Three methods of ethics (pp. 3–91). Oxford: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Batson, C. D. (1991). The altruism question: Toward a social-psychological answer. Hillsdale: Erlbaum

    Google Scholar 

  • Benner, D. (1979) Lässt sich das Technologieproblem durch eine Ersatztechnologie lösen? eine Auseinandersetzung mit N. Luhmann und K.-E. Schorrs Thesen zum Technologiedefizit der Erziehung [Can the technology problem be solved by a technology of replacement? A debate with N. Luhmann and K-E. Schorr on the technological deficit of education]. Zeitschrift für Pädagogik. Journal of Pedagogy, 25(3), 367–375

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben Ze’ev, A. (2000). The subtlety of emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben Ze’ev, A. (2001). Are envy, anger, and resentment moral emotions? Philosophical Explorations, 5(2), 148–154

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum, L. A. (1980a). Compassion. In A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Explaining emotions (pp. 506–517). Berkeley: University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum, L. A. (1980b). Friendship, altruism and morality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. L. (2005) Today, moral identity; tomorrow, self-esteem? Applied Developmental Psychology, 26, 235–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1996). After Kohlberg. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 15, 353–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (2005). On the contribution of literature and the arts to the educational cultivation of moral virtue, feeling and emotion. Journal of Moral Education, 34(2), 137–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D., & Steutel, J. (1999). Virtue ethics and the virtue approach to moral education. In D.Carr, & J. Steutel (Eds.), Virtue ethics and moral education (pp. 3–18). London: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, J. B., & Townsend, M. A. R. (1990). The effects of training in social perspective taking on socially maladjusted girls. Child Development, 61, 178–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chodorow, N. (1978). The reproduction of mothering: Psychoanalysis and the sociology of gender. Berkeley: University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J. (Ed.) (1999). Educating minds and hearts: Social and emotional learning and thepassage into adolescence. New York: Teachers College Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J. (Ed.) (2001). Caring classrooms/intelligent school: The social emotional education of young children. New York: Teachers College Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. H. (1994). Empathy: A social psychological approach. Madison: Brown & Benchmark

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1649/1984). The passions of the soul. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, & A. Kenny (Trans. and Eds.), The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

  • de Sousa, R. (1987). The rationality of emotions. Cambridge: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa, R. (2001). Moral emotions. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 4, 109–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelstein, W., & Fauser, P. (2001). Demokratie lernen und leben: Materialen zur Bildungsplanung und zur Forschungsförderung [Learning and living democracy: Material for educational planning and the advancement of research]. (Bonn: Bund-Länder-Kommission für Bildungsplanung und zur Forschungsförderung)

  • Eisenberg, N., & Miller, P. (1987a). Empathy, sympathy and altruism: Empirical and conceptual links. In N. Eisenberg, & J. Strayer (Eds.), Empathy and its development (pp. 292–316). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, N., & Miller, P. (1987b). The relation of empathy to prosocial and related behaviours. Psychological Bulletin, 101, 91–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elias, M. J., Zins, J. E., Weissberg, R. P., Frey, K. S., Greenberg, M. T., Haynes, N. M., Kessler, R., Schwab-Stone, M. E., & Shriver T. P. (1997). Promoting social and emotional learning: guidelines for educators. Alexandria: ASCD

    Google Scholar 

  • Epictetus (1st century C.E./1925). Discourses. W.A. Oldfather (Ed. and Trans.). Harvard: Harvard University Press

  • Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 67(1), 5–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. (1992). Descartes’ metaphysical physics. Chicago: Chicago University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, J. (2003). Moral development and reality: Beyond the theories of Kohlberg and Hoffman. Thousand Oaks: Sage

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Goleman, D. (1995). Emotional intelligence: Why it can matter more than IQ. New York: Bantam Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, M. (1995). Releasing the imagination: Essays on education, the arts and social change. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, J.J. (1998). The emerging field of emotional regulation: an integrative review. Review of General Psychology, 2, 271–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossman, D. C., Neckerman, H. J., Koepsell, T. D., Liu, P. Y., Asher, K. N., Beland, K., Frey, K., & Rivara, F. P. (1997). Effectiveness of a violence prevention curriculum among children in elementary school: A randomized controlled trial. Journal of the American Medical Association, 277, 1605–1611

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herman, B. (1996). The practice of moral judgment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, T. (2000). Respect, pluralism and justice: Kantian perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M. (1981). Is altruism part of human nature? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 40, 121–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M. L. (2000) Empathy and moral development: Implications for caring and justice. New York: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hügli, A. (1999). Philosophie und Pädagogik [Philosophy and pedagogy]. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1751/1957). Inquiry concerning the principles of morals. New York: Prentice Hall

  • Kilpatrick, W. (1992). Why Johnny can’t tell right from wrong. New York: Simon & Schuster

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1978). The cognitive-developmental approach to moral education. In P. Scharf (Ed.), Readings in moral education (pp. 36–51). Minneapolis: Winston Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1999). Self-constitution in the ethics of Kant and Plato. Journal of Ethics, 3, 1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2003). Fortunes-of-others emotions and justice. Journal of Philosophical Research, 28, 107–130

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2005). Can we teach justified anger? Journal of Philosophy of Education, 39(4), 671–689

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lapsley, D. K., & Narváez, D. (2005). Moral psychology at the crossroads. In D. Lapsley, & F. C. Power (Eds.), Character psychology and character education (pp. 18–35). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lao Tzu (6th century B.C.E./2000). In S. Mitchell (Ed.), Tao teaching: The book of the way. London: Kyle Cathie

  • Lickona, T. (1992). Educating for character: How our schools can teach respect and responsibility. New York: Bantam

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N., & Schorr, K. E. (1982). Das Technologiedefizit der Erziehung und die Pädagogik [The technological deficit of education and pedagogy]. In N. Luhmann, & K.-E. Schorr (Eds.), Zwischen Technologie und Selbstreferenz [Between technology and self-reference] (pp. 11–40). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp

  • MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, B., & Reichenbach, R. (2005). Imitation, imagination and re-appraisal: educating the moral emotions. Journal of Moral Education, 34(2), 291–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, C. (2005). Character possession and human flourishing. In D. Lapsley, & F. C. Power (Eds.), Character psychology and character education (pp. 36–66). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, T., & Halstead, M. (1999). Education in character, virtue. In M. Halstead, T. McLaughlin (Eds.), Education in morality (pp. 132–163). London: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahon, S. D., Washburn, J., Felix, E. D., Yakin, J., & Childrey, G. (2000). Violence prevention: Program effects on urban preschool and kindergarten children. Applied and Preventive Psychology, 9, 271–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercer, P. (1972). Sympathy and ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1970). The possibility of altruism. Oxford: Clarendon Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1887/2003). The genealogy of morals. London: Dover

  • Noddings, N. (1984). Caring: A feminine approach to ethics & moral education. Berkeley: University of California Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. (1990). The challenge to care in schools. New York: Teachers College Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. (1998). Thinking, feeling and moral imagination. In P. French, & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy (Vol. 22, pp. 134–145). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1995). Poetic justice. Boston: Beacon Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of the emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Papillo: Ein Programm zur Vorbeugung gegen die Entwicklung von Sucht- und Gewalt -verhalten [Papillo: An addiction and violence prevention programme]. Heidrun Mayer, Director. Beta Institut. Retrieved 24 February 2006 <http://www.papilio.de/>

  • Peters, R. S. (1981). The place of Kohlberg’s theory in moral education. In Moral development and moral education (pp. 166–182). London: George Allen & Unwin

  • Reichenbach, R. (2001). Demokratisches Selbst und dilettantisches Subjekt Demokratische Bildung und Erziehung in der Spätmoderne [The democratic self and the dilettante subject: teaching and education in late modernity]. Münster: Waxmann

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau. J.-J. (1754/1992). Discourse on the origins of inequality. D.A. Cress (Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett

  • Rousseau. J.-J. (1762/1979). Émile. A. Bloom (Trans.). New York: Basic Books

  • Scheler M. (1954). The nature of sympathy. P. Heath (Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul

  • Second Step: A Violence Prevention Curriculum. Debra Boyer, President. Committee for Children. Retrieved 24 February 2006 <http://www.cfchildren.org/cfc/ssf/ssf/ ssindex/>

  • Selman, R. L. (1980). The growth of interpersonal understanding: Developmental and clinical analyses. New York: Academic Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Seneca (1st century C.E./1969). Letters from a Stoic. R. Campbell (Ed. and Trans.). London: Penguin

  • Sherman, N. (1990). The place of emotions Kantian morality. In O. Flanagan, & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Identity, character and morality (pp. 149–179). Cambridge: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1790/1976). Theory of moral sentiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Steutel, J., & Spiecker, B. (2004). Cultivating sentimental dispositions through Aristotelian habituation. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 38(4), 531–549

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self. Harvard: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Verducci, S. (2000). A moral method? Thoughts on cultivating empathy through method acting. Journal of Moral Education, 29(1), 87–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vetlesen, A. J. (1994). Perception, empathy, and judgment: An inquiry into the preconditions of moral performance. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice. New York: Basic Books

    Google Scholar 

  • Webster-Stratton, C. (1999). How to promote children’s social and emotional competence. London: Sage

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

Special thanks go to Tina Malti for her expert help in our attempt to situate the ideas in paper within the context of contemporary research in social psychology on emotional development and education.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bruce Maxwell.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Maxwell, B., Reichenbach, R. Educating moral emotions: a praxiological analysis. Stud Philos Educ 26, 147–163 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-006-9020-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-006-9020-4

Keywords

Navigation