Skip to main content
Log in

Art history, the problem of style, and Arnold Hauser’s contribution to the history and sociology of knowledge

  • Published:
Studies in East European Thought Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Much of Arnold Hauser’s work on the social history of art and the philosophy of art history is informed by a concern for the cognitive dimension of art. The present paper offers a reconstruction of this aspect of Hauser’s project and identifies areas of overlap with the sociology of knowledge—where the latter is to be understood as both a separate discipline and a going intellectual concern. Following a discussion of Hauser’s personal and intellectual background, as well as of the shifting political and academic setting of his work, the paper addresses one of Hauser’s central questions, viz. how best to square a thoroughgoing commitment to the social nature of art with the reality of successive artistic styles, given that the latter seem to be characterizable on purely formal grounds. This is followed by a discussion of Hauser’s conflicted views on the relation between art, science, and technology. This injects a tension into Hauser’s work, due to his initial reluctance to explain just how the aesthetic and the cognitive realms relate. The final part of the paper, through a closer examination of the analogies and disanalogies that Hauser sees between art history and the history of science, attempts to give a positive answer—“on Hauser’s behalf”, as it were—to the question of whether art may be credited with a specific cognitive dimension of its own, and if so, what its contribution to our cognitive enterprise may consist in.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On Hauser’s distinction between aesthetics and the theory and sociology of art, see also (Demeter 2008: 7).

  2. All page numbers in the remainder of this section refer to The Philosophy of Art History (Hauser 1959).

  3. For a critique of Wölfflin’s divorcing of the scholarly methods of art history from those of cultural history, see also (Wind 1931).

  4. This foreshadows Paul Feyerabend’s argument that “there are no ‘neutral’ objects which can be represented in any style, and which can be used as objective arbiters between radically different styles” (Feyerabend 1975: 23); see also the section “Art, technology, and scientific knowledge.”

  5. This is confirmed by Hauser’s reiteration of the point in The Sociology of Art: “In this sense, we can maintain that the sciences, especially the formal ones like logic or mathematics, have no ‘actual’ history and that as far as they are concerned it is more proper to speak of a history of errors and misunderstandings than of one with positive results.” (Hauser 1982: 85) Debates within the history of science, following Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), seem to have had no impact on Hauser’s thinking. Interestingly, Kuhn himself acknowledges the influence that debates in art history have had on his own thinking (Kuhn 1969: 403). An anonymous referee raised doubts about the extent of this influence, by noting that Kuhn cautioned art historians not to think of styles as paradigms: “If the notion of paradigm can be useful to the art historian, it will be pictures not styles that serve as paradigms.” (Kuhn 1969: 412) However, this criticism overlooks two important points. First, Kuhn’s warning against the misuse of the term “paradigm” in art historian circles coincides with his (failed) attempts, in this and other 1969 papers, to establish, once and for all, a narrow meaning of the term “paradigm” in philosophy of science, namely as referring to (individual) “exemplars” (hence his analogy with “pictures” in art history)—as opposed to the more expansive notion of a “disciplinary matrix”. (See Hoyningen-Huene 1993: 142.) Second, Kuhn’s rejection of equating “style” with “paradigm” is, in actuality, a rejection of talk about “theory”:

    Both ‘style’ and ‘theory’ are terms used when describing a group of works which are recognizably similar. (They are ‘in the same style’ or ‘applications of the same theory’.) In both cases it proves difficult—I think ultimately impossible—to specify the nature of the shared elements which distinguish a given style or a given theory from another. (Kuhn 1969: 412)

    Thus, Kuhn’s real target is a reified notion of “style” that would be quite alien to Hauser—who, as shown in the previous section, attempts to rescue the concept of “style” from those who would like to attribute to it the status of a “‘higher’, Platonic, or Hegelian idea” (Hauser 1959: 213). On the link between iconography, the concept of artistic style, and Kuhn’s philosophy of science, see also (Fuller 2000: 51–77).

References

  • Burke, P. (2008). What is cultural history? London: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Congdon, L. (2004). Arnold Hauser and the retreat from Marxism. In T. Demeter (Ed.), Essays on Wittgenstein and Austrian philosophy (pp. 41–61). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeter, T. (2008). The sociological tradition of Hungarian philosophy. Studies in East European Thought, 60, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forgács, É. (2008). The safe haven of a new classicism: The quest for a new aesthetics in Hungary 1904–1912. Studies in East European Thought, 60, 75–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2000). Thomas Kuhn: A philosophical history for our times. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2010). Kant and the Enlightenment’s contribution to social epistemology. Episteme, 7, 79–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gluck, M. (1985). Georg Lukács and his generation 1900–1918. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. H. (Ed.), (1963). The social history of art. In Meditations on a hobby horse and other essays on the theory of art (pp. 86–94). London: Phaidon Press.

  • Hauser, A. (1951). The social history of art. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Originally 2 vols.; citations follow the four-volume paperback edition 1962).

  • Hauser, A. (1959). The philosophy of art history. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, A. (1965). Mannerism: The crisis of the Renaissance and the origin of modern art. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, A. (1978). Találkozásaim Lukács Györggyel. Budapest: Akadémiai Kiadó.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, A. (1982). The sociology of art. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing scientific revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s philosophy of science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, W. M. (1983). The Austrian mind: An intellectual and social history 1848–1938. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1969). Comment [on The new reality in art and science], Comparative Studies in Society and History 11, 403–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannheim, K. (1956). Essays on the sociology of culture. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orwicz, M. (1985). Critical discourse in the formation of a social history of art: Anglo-American response to Arnold Hauser. Oxford Art Journal, 8, 52–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, J. (2006). Arnold Hauser, Adorno, Lukács and the ideal spectator. In A. Hemingway (Ed.), Marxism and the history of art: From William Norris to the new left (pp. 161–174). London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, G. (1978). The philosophy of money (trans: Bottomore, T., Frisby, D.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Swanson, G. W. (1996). Marx, Weber, and the crisis of reality in Arnold Hauser’s. Sociology of Art. The European Legacy, 1, 2199–2214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (1996). Art, autonomy, and heteronomy: The provocation of Arnold Hauser’s The Social History of Art, Thesis Eleven, 44, 28–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wessely, A. (1995). The reader’s progress: Remarks on Arnold Hauser’s philosophy of art history. In K. Gavroglu, J. Stachel, & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Science, mind and art: Essays on science and the humanistic understanding in art, epistemology, religion and ethics (pp. 29–43). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wind, E. (1931). Warburgs Begriff der Kulturwissenschaft und seine Bedeutung für die Ästhetik. Vierter Kongreß für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Supplement to Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, 25, 163–179.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Axel Gelfert.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gelfert, A. Art history, the problem of style, and Arnold Hauser’s contribution to the history and sociology of knowledge. Stud East Eur Thought 64, 121–142 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-012-9163-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-012-9163-5

Keywords

Navigation