Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Abstract

How does a Muslim jurist think the law and how, accordingly, he judges a fact? Using Alice in Wonderland as hermeneutical device to explore the logic of fiqh, this article identifies a divergence between Western and Islamic legal thinking in the application of abduction as key form of inference in the law of Islam. In particular, looking at the fact/law relation in symbolic terms, the article highlights how, while a dichotomy between fact and law characterizes Western legal thinking, fiqh upholds a connection between the “real” and the “right” (ḥaqq), where the effort (ijtihād) in understanding sharī‘ah postulates the actualization of the “rule” (ḥukm) in God’s creation. Thus, if sharī‘ah pre-scribes the Law, not only is the rule discovered through the sources (uṣūl), but the right has to be justified through a verdict de-scribing the fact, for the law to be validly stated for the given situation. In this sense, abduction as explanatory “hypothesis” (Peirce) and “inference to the best explanation” (Harman) of sharī‘ah provides an account for the probabilistic nature of fiqh, its ramification (furū‘) through verdicts, as well as for the epistemic and narrative function of the tradition as core aspects of the logic of Islamic law. At the same time, doubts can be raised about the compatibility between this logic and the deductive logic of modern state law, as a sub-product of Western legal thinking.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As well-known, Lewis Carroll (pseudonym of Charles Lutwidge Dodgson, 1832–1898), wrote his novel to collect the fantasy stories that he invented for little Alice Liddell during a boat trip in Oxford. For a comprehensive portrait of Alice’s world, see Gardner [14].

  2. The verb “to judge” is used here in the sense of “assessing”, “evaluating” the fact in order to define its legal qualification and derive/discover the legal effects from the revealed sources. The intellectual activity of the Muslim jurist can result in a legal opinion (fatwā) or be related to the judiciary, when he acts as qāḍī.

  3. The adoption of Western law as “study-language” to investigate non-Western “targets” constitutes, in my opinion, the issue par excellence of comparative law methodology. In this sense, Norman Calder notes how “Western scholarship (even when written by Muslims) has rarely presented Islamic law in such a way as to demonstrate its value rather than the values of the observer” [7, p. 979].

  4. Following the Austro-Hungarian scholar Eugen Erlich, the sociological approach theorizes the likely divergence between the theory and practice of law. In this regard, Palmer remarks how “Roscoe Pound’s essay on Law in Books and Law in Action immediately followed Erlich’s work and Max Weber stressed that formal law is often modified or subverted at the level of application” [39, p. 283].

  5. A doctrine dealing with “the nature of signs the mind makes use of for the understanding of things, or conveying its knowledge to others” [30, p. 461].

  6. In fact, “the representamen and its semiotic object are mediated by a third term, the interpretant. As a result of such mediation, the sign takes on value, meaning, and importance as a representamen doing its thing along with its neighbors within the vast river of semiosis—the process of signs becoming other signs” [33, p. 34].

  7. “From the perspective of the Muslim jurist, legal theory can be regarded as the “science of proofs”, leading to standards that regulate human actions. These standards derive primarily from a discovery… of the aḥkām, the qualification… or, more specifically, God’s determination of the moral value of individual acts” [50, p. 33].

  8. “To Him is due the primal origin of the heavens and earth. When He decreeth a matter, He saith only “Be,” and it is” (Qur’ān II:117) (see also Qur’ān III:47, 59; VI:73; XVI:40; XXXVI:82; XL:68). In this sense, the word “will” is also expressed by “the term mashī’ah, “volition”, and so it is that the word shay’, “thing”, deriving from the same root, is sometimes glossed as “what has been willed [by God] to exist” [38, p. 192].

  9. “The occasion is, of course, preceded by an order to do something. But… it is nevertheless the occasion that brings the duty into effect and not the command” [42, p. 197].

  10. The dogma of the absolute sovereignty of God is linked to an atomistic conception of time, inserting the flow of human contingent agencies in the eternal creativeness of God. Accordingly, al-Ghazālī upheld that “the world comes to be at the time when the eternal… stands in nexus with its coming-to-be” [38, p. 193]. God’s personal command, “Be! and it is” (kun fa-yakūn) governs any event in time: “Allāh is the Lord of each instant” [5, p. 58].

  11. Similarly to Geertz, Hallaq stresses how in Islam “the physical world is not a scientific site subject to cold and bland rational explanation and calculation but rather a natural world saturated with spirituality and psychology, one wholly subservient to moral actions taken by the very humans that were created by God” [19, p. 84].

  12. A term that he claimed corresponds to what Aristotle describes in Prior Analytics, II, ch. 25 (CP: 7.249) [41].

  13. “[W]hereas deduction and induction were demoted to merely phases of testing an already formed hypothesis” [11, p. 471].

  14. “What one quickly finds is that legal theory manuals are dedicated neither to the induction of principles nor the deduction of injunctions, for both are considered already resolved” [2, p. 6].

  15. To my knowledge, Ahmed’s book is the first work on Islamic law to refer explicitly to Peirce’s abduction to explain the logic of fiqh, prior to the present study.

  16. Since the verse al-Baqarah 283 exclusively refers to evidentiary problems arising from the parties’ inability to record a contract away from urban centres.

  17. “Explanatory considerations” that are not necessarily based on available revelatory sources, but can also be grounded on “juristic preference” (see § 4.2.1).

  18. Zakāt as (2.1) a personal duty to God; (2.2) a communal duty implemented by the Imām; (2.3) a functional provision for the poor.

  19. Deductive reasoning does not exclude that also induction (especially in common law countries) and abduction appear in Western law [17]. But, with specific regard to modern state law, the centrality of the rule as “major premise” (“established”, positum, by state sovereignty), however it later intervenes in the formulation of the judgment, represents an element that cannot be denied (§ 5).

  20. Johansen specifically refers to al-Sarakhsī (d. 1096 AD)’s Mabsūṭ and al-Kāsānī (d. 1191 AD)’s Badā’i‘‘l-Ṣanā’ī‘in his study.

  21. “Max Weber… opposes what he calls “substantive rationality” (materiale Rationalität) to “formal rationality” (formale Rationalität). Substantive rationality dominates a sacred law in which ethical imperatives, political maxims or utilitarian rules of expediency are developed into norms or general principles and take the place which… the logical generalization of abstract principles [as part of a coherent system] occupy in a law which is characterized by the “formal rationality”” [24, pp. 49–50].

References

  1. Abd-Allah, U.F. 2008. Theological dimensions of Islamic law. In The Cambridge companion to classical Islamic theology, ed. T. Winter, 237–257. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Ahmed, R. 2012. Narratives of Islamic legal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. Ainsworth, J.E. 1996. Categories and culture: on the ‘reification of names’ in comparative law. Cornell Law Review 82: 19–42.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Al-Alwani, T.J. 1999. Uṣūl al-fiqh al Islāmī. Source methodology in Islamic jurisprudence, 3rd ed. London: Zain International.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Böwering, G. 1997. The concept of time in Islam. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 141(1): 55–66.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Buskens, L., and B. Dupret. 2011. L’invention du droit musulman. Genèse et diffusion du positivisme juridique dans le contexte normative islamique. In Après l’orientalism. L’Orient créé par l’Orient, ed. F. Pouillon, and J.C. Vatin, 71–92. Paris: Karthala.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Calder, N. 1996. Law. In History of Islamic philosophy, ed. S.H. Nasr, and O. Leaman, 979–998. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Carroll, L. 1865. Alice’s adventures in wonderland. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Chehata, C. 1965. Études de philosophie musulmane du droit. I. Logique juridique et droit musulman. Studia Islamica 23: 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. De Waal, C. 2013. Peirce. A guide for the perplexed. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Deutscher, G. 2002. On the misuse of the notion of ‘abduction’ in linguistics. Journal of Linguistics 38(3): 469–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Fadel, M. 2002. Istiḥsān is nine-tenths of the law: the puzzling relationship of uṣūl to furū‘in the Mālikī madhhab. In Studies in Islamic legal theory, ed. B.G. Weiss, 161–176. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Flanagan, O. 1992. Consciousness reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gardner, M. 2000. The annotated Alice: Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland and Through the Looking-Glass. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Geertz, C. 1983. Local Knowledge: Fact and law in a comparative perspective. In Local knowledge. Further essays in interpretive anthropology, ed. C. Geertz, 167–234. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Glenn, H.P. 2000. Legal traditions of the world. Sustainable diversity in law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gorlée, D.L. 2005. Hints and guesses: Legal modes of semio-logical reasoning. Sign Systems Studies 33(2): 239–272.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Hallaq, W.B. 2009. An introduction to Islamic law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Hallaq, W.B. 2014. The impossible state: Islam, politics, and modernity’s moral predicament. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Harman, G.H. 1965. The inference to the best explanation. The Philosophical Review 74(1): 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Iranzo, V. 2007. Abduction and inference to the best explanation. Theoria 60: 339–346.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Jackson, S. 2002. Fiction and formalism: towards a functional analysis of uṣūl al-fiqh. In Studies in Islamic legal theory, ed. B.G. Weiss, 177–201. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Johansen, B. 1995. Casuistry: Between legal concept and social praxis. Islamic Law and Society 2(2): 135–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Johansen, B. 1999. Contingency in a sacred law: Legal and ethical norms in the Muslim fiqh. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Johnston, D. 2004. A turn in the epistemology and hermeneutics of twentieth century uṣul al-fiqh. Islamic Law and Society 11(2): 233–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Kamali, M.H. 1993. Fundamental rights of the individual: an analysis of ḥaqq (right) in Islamic law. The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 10(3): 340–366.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kelsen, H. 1945. General theory of law and state. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kevelson, R. (ed.). 1991. Peirce and law: Issues in pragmatism, legal realism, and semiotics. New York: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lipton, P. 2004. Inference to the best explanation, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Locke, J. 1959. An essay concerning human understanding. Ed. A.C. Fraser, New York: Dover Publications & Constable.

  31. MacCormick, N. 1978. Legal reasoning and legal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. MacDonald, D.B. [-Calverley, E.E.] 1975. Ḥaqq. In Encyclopédie de l'Islam, II Ed., Tome III, 84–85. Leiden: Brill, and Paris: Maisonneuve & Larose.

  33. Merrell, F. 2001. Charles Sanders Peirce’s concept of the sign. In The Routledge companion to semiotics and linguistics, ed. P. Cobley, 28–39. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Merry, S.E. 1988. Legal pluralism. Law and Society Review 22(5): 869–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Moosa, E. 1998. Allegory of the rule (ḥukm): law as simulacrum in Islam? History of Religions 38(1): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Netton, I.R. 1989. Allah transcendent: Studies in the structure and semiotics of Islamic philosophy, theology and cosmology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Opwis, F. 2005. Maṣlaḥa in contemporary Islamic legal theory. Islamic Law and Society 12(2): 182–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Ormsby, E.L. 1984. Theodicy in Islamic thought. The dispute over al-Ghazālī’s “Best of All Possible Worlds”. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Palmer, V.V. 2005. From Lerotholi to Lando: some examples of comparative law methodology. The American Journal of Comparative Law 53(1): 261–290.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Pardo, M.S., and R.J. Allen. 2008. Juridical proof and the best explanation. Law and Philosophy 27: 223–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Peirce, C.S. 1931–1958. Collected Papers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  42. Reinhart, A.K. 1983. Islamic law as Islamic ethics. Journal of Religious Ethics 11(2): 186–203.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Reinhart, A.K., and R. Gleave (eds.). 2014. Islamic law in theory. Studies on jurisprudence in honor of Bernard Weiss. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Sadeghi, B. 2013. The logic of law making in Islam: Women and prayer in the legal tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  45. Santos, B.D.S. 1987. Law: A map of misreading. Towards a postmodern conception of law. Journal of Law and Society 14(3): 279–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Saussure, F. de 1916. Cours de linguistique générale. Ed. C. Bally, and A., Sechehaye, Lausanne-Paris: Payot.

  47. Stelzer, S.A.J. 2008. Ethics. In The Cambridge companion to classical Islamic theology, ed. T. Winter, 161–179. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  48. Szymborska, W. 1996. View with a grain of sand. Selected poems. Transl. by S. Barańczak and C. Cavanagh. London: Faber and Faber.

  49. Van der Helm, A.J., and V.M. Meyer. 1991. Comparer en droit. Essai méthodologique. Strasbourg: Cerdic Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Wakin, J. 1990. Interpretation of the divine command in the jurisprudence of Muwaffaq al-Dīn Ibn Qudāmah. In Islamic law and jurisprudence. Studies in honor of Farhat J. Ziadeh, ed. N. Heer, 33–52. London: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Wehr, H. 1994. Arabic-English dictionary. Dictionary of modern written Arabic. Ed. J.M. Cowan, 4th ed. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz.

  52. Weiss, B.G. (ed.). 2002. Studies in Islamic legal theory. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valentino Cattelan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cattelan, V. Alice’s Adventures, Abductive Reasoning and the Logic of Islamic Law. Int J Semiot Law 29, 359–388 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-016-9459-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-016-9459-8

Keywords

Navigation