Skip to main content
Log in

Not Such Nature

Stephen K. Sanderson (2014) Human Nature and the Evolution of Society. Westview Press, Boulder, CO, ISBN: 978-0-8133-4937-4, 349 pages, $60.00 (paperback)

  • Book Review
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. It is possible that the main point of conflict between the humanities and the biological approaches to the study of human behavior lies not in the friction between a false model of tabula rasa (SSSM) and a model where universal modules govern behavior (ICM). In retrospective, evolutionary psychology made indeed a proper critique of the idea that the cognitive mechanisms are basically free of informational content. The richer in content a cognitive mechanism is, the more specialized is its functioning. If the operation and structure of a cognitive mechanism (neural module) are dependent on, and vary with its informational content, and vice versa, then functionalism falls apart: the independence between structure and function breaks down (Churchland 2005). Basically, this is a critique of Cartesianism, a critique of the incommensurability between the body (biological neural mechanisms) and the mind (dominated by “immaterial" cultural processes). This critique of Cartesianism, however, is much older than the emergence of evolutionary psychology, consisting itself in an inner movement within the human sciences (e.g., Merleau-Ponty 1942, pp. 287–345; Merleau-Ponty 1945, pp. 493–548). In turn, to say that mind and body are effectively interconnected does not imply that they are one single phenomenon, nor does it mean that one predominates over the other; i.e., the interdependence thesis does not imply that biological phenomena (the factor for body construction) dominate cultural phenomena (the inputs of informational content), or vice-versa. No one doubts, for example, that individuals do change as a function of the relationships they establish within their social group. Thus, even if Cartesian dualism is dead, one has to recognize a tension between the causalities that run from the individual to the upper levels of organization (and in this way make up the social tissue) and the causalities that run down from the social tissue and, in this way, impart form to the individual.

  2. Complexity sciences comprise a remarkably interdisciplinary field of research, dealing with how properties of a system emerge from the interaction of its constituent parts, thus explaining how the parts engage in collective behavior. Researchers from disparate fields, such as economics, biology, chemistry, physics, and others, build on statistical physics and nonlinear dynamics to model complex, natural systems. Usually, the recursive and nonlinear nature of the interactions within the system, and also between the system and its surroundings, lead to the emergence of organized and unpredictable collective behavior.

  3. Darwin obviously does not advocate for group selection, or kin selection, since these theories arose much later in the history of evolutionary thought. The discussion is about the compatibility of Darwinian thought with these views about the selection process. In kin selection, the units of selection are the genes: some alleles are more successful than others; besides that, it may be advantageous to help relatives because this helps perpetuate the common genetics that unites the interactors. In group selection, the selection unit is the group: some groups are more successful than others, and so some groups propagate more than others. Darwin (1874) explicitly writes that "A tribe including many members who, from possessing in a high degree the spirit of patriotism, fidelity, obedience, courage, and sympathy, were always ready to aid one another, and to sacrifice themselves for the common good, would be victorious over most other tribes; and this would be natural selection”. It is clear in this passage that the difference between the tribes is the relevant factor. To make this interpretation even more straightforward, ruling out individuals as the unit of selection, Darwin explains in the same paragraph that "It must not be forgotten that although the high standard of morality gives but a slight or no advantage to each individual man and his children over the other men of the same tribe, yet that an increase in the number of well-endowed men and an advancement in the standard of morality will certainly give an immense advantage to one tribe over another”. There seems to be clear, looking at both quotes together, that Darwin considers the tribes as the main locus of fitness differences (some groups are more successful than others: group selection), and that for him fitness differences between individuals seem less relevant when it comes to explaining the evolution of these moral behaviors.

References

  • Andrews, T. (2012). What is social constructionism. The Grounded Theory Review, 11(1), 39–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avital, E., & Jablonka, E. (2000). Animal traditions: Behavioural inheritance in evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L. E., & Tooby, J. E. (1992). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard, A. (2011). Social anthropology and human origins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beurton, P. J., Falk, R., & Rheinberger, H. J. (Eds.). (2000). The concept of the gene in development and evolution: Historical and epistemological perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blount, Z. D., Borland, C. Z., & Lenski, R. E. (2008). Historical contingency and the evolution of a key innovation in an experimental population of Escherichia coli. PNAS, 105(23), 7899–7906.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolhuis, J. J., Brown, G. R., Richardson, R. C., & Laland, K. N. (2011). Darwin in mind: New opportunities for evolutionary psychology. PLoS Biology, 9(7), e1001109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buhl, J., Sumpter, D. J., Couzin, I. D., Hale, J. J., Despland, E., Miller, E. R., & Simpson, S. J. (2006). From disorder to order in marching locusts. Science, 312(5778), 1402–1406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. J. (2005). Adapting minds: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. M. (2010). Selection does not operate primarily on genes. In F. J. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 141–164). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, R. W., & Whiten, A. (1989). Machiavellian intelligence: Social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes, and humans. Oxford: Oxford Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cabej, N. (2012). Epigenetic principles of evolution. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(5), 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S. P., Hendry, A. P., Reznick, D. N., & Fox, C. W. (2007). Evolution on ecological time-scales. Functional Ecology, 21(3), 387–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (2005). Functionalism at forty: A critical retrospective. Journal of philosophy, 102(1), 33–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Couzin, I. D., & Krause, J. (2003). Self-organization and collective behavior in vertebrates. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 32, 1–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. R. (1874). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex (2nd ed.). London: John Murray.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, M. W., & Laland, K. N. (1996). Gene-culture coevolutionary theory. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 11(11), 453–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoglund, J. (1996). Can mating systems affect local extinction risks? Two examples of lek-breeding waders. Oikos, 77, 184–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. (1999). Dynamics in action: Intentional behavior as a complex system (Vol. 31). Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korb, J., & Foster, K. R. (2010). Ecological competition favours cooperation in termite societies. Ecology Letters, 13, 754–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, J., & Feldman, M. W. (2001). Cultural niche construction and human evolution. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 14(1), 22–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland K. N., Uller, T., Feldman, M. W., Sterelny, K., Müller, G. B., Moczek, A., et al. (2015). The extended evolutionary synthesis: Its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proceedings of The Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 282, 20151019.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layton, R. (2010). Why social scientists don’t like Darwin and what can be done about it. Journal of Evolutionary Psychology, 8(2), 139–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, X., Rong, S., & Queller, D. C. (2015). Relatedness, conflict, and the evolution of eusociality. PLoS Biology, 13(3), e1002098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2015). Conceptual change in biology: Scientific and philosophical perspectives on evolution and development (Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science: 307). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1994 [1945]). Fenomenologia da percepção. Martins Fontes, São Paulo.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2006 [1942]). A estrutura do comportamento. Martins Fontes, São Paulo.

  • Müller, G. B. (2007). Evo–devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics, 8(12), 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M. A., Tarnita, C. E., & Wilson, E. O. (2010). The evolution of eusociality. Nature, 466, 1057–1062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F. J., Laland, K. N., & Feldman, M. W. (2003). Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution (No. 37). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Müller, G. B. (Eds.). (2010). Evolution, the extended synthesis. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rankin, D. J., Lopez-Sepulcre, A., Foster, K. R., & Kokko, H. (2007). Species-level selection reduces selfishness through competitive exclusion. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 20, 1459–1468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2008). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., Boyd, R., & Henrich, J. (2010). Gene-culture coevolution in the age of genomics. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(Supplement 2), 8985–8992.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schradin, C. (2013). Intraspecific variation in social organization by genetic variation, developmental plasticity, social flexibility or entirely extrinsic factors. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 368(1618), 20120346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., & Lewontin, R. (1982). Artifact, cause, and genic selectionism. Philosophy of Science, 49, 157–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sumpter, D. J. (2010). Collective animal behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tarde, G. (2012 [1893]). Monadology and sociology. Melbourne: Re.press.

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1990). The past explains the present: Emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11(4), 375–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsuji, K., & Dobata, S. (2011). Social cancer and the biology of the clonal ant Pristomyrmex punctatus (hymenoptera: Formicidae). Myrmecology News, 15, 91–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., & Byrne, R. W. (Eds.). (1997). Machiavellian intelligence II: Extensions and evaluations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. (1980). Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery: Case studies (pp. 213–259). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank Charbel Niño El-Hani and Kostas Kampourakis for comments and criticisms that improved the manuscript. This contribution is part of a visiting professor stay at the University of St Andrews and benefited from a CNPq scholarship (232691/2014-2).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hilton F. Japyassú.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Japyassú, H.F. Not Such Nature. Sci & Educ 24, 1271–1283 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-015-9777-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-015-9777-3

Navigation