Skip to main content
Log in

Teaching About Adaptation: Why Evolutionary History Matters

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Adaptation is one of the central concepts in evolutionary theory, which nonetheless has been given different definitions. Some scholars support a historical definition of adaptation, considering it as a trait that is the outcome of natural selection, whereas others support an ahistorical definition, considering it as a trait that contributes to the survival and reproduction of its possessors. Finally, adaptation has been defined as a process, as well. Consequently, two questions arise: the first is a philosophical one and focuses on what adaptation actually is; the second is a pedagogical one and focuses on what science teachers and educators should teach about it. In this article, the various definitions of adaptation are discussed and their uses in some textbooks are presented. It is suggested that, given elementary students’ intuitions about purpose and design in nature and secondary students’ teleological explanations for the origin of adaptations, any definition of adaptation as a trait should include some information about its evolutionary history.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The terms ‘ahistorical’ and ‘non-historical’ have been used to describe the same type of definition. Although, they may be considered as synonyms, in this article I use the term ‘ahistorical’ because it is closer to the etymological origins of the term.

  2. This is what is usually described as fitness. However, this is another ambiguous or at least potentially confusing term (see Ariew and Lewontin 2004). Thus, in order to avoid dealing with this concept as well, the term fitness is not used in this article. Instead of describing adaptations as traits that contribute to increased fitness, I will refer to them as traits that contribute to the survival and reproduction of their possessors.

  3. Note the use of teleological language at this point: selection of a trait for a role. To non-experts this might seem like selection of a trait in order to perform a role. However, philosophers use it in another sense: selection of a trait because it performs a role. Given the discussion that will follow it is useful to keep this difference in mind.

  4. For the history of the concept see Amudson (1996).

References

  • Amudson, R. (1996). Historical development of the concept of adaptation. In M. R. Rose & G. V. Lauder (Eds.), Adaptation (pp. 11–53). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A., & Lewontin, R. C. (2004). The confusions of fitness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 347–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audesirk, T., Audesirk, G., & Byers, B. E. (2002). Biology: Life on earth (6th ed.). New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avise, J. C. (2010). Inside the human genome: A case for non-intelligent design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy, CIII(7), 336–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P., & Weisberg, D. S. (2007). Childhood origins of adult resistance to science. Science, 316, 996–997.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bock, W. J. (1980). The definition and recognition of biological adaptation. American Zoologist, 20(1), 217–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (2003). Evolution: The history of an idea (3rd ed.). Berkeley and Los Angeles, California: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. N. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. M. (1992). Adaptation: Historical perspectives. In E. F. Keller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 7–12). Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, England: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N. A., & Reece, J. B. (2005). Biology (7th ed.). San Francisco: Pearson Education- Benjamin Cummings.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (2002). Neo-teleology. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions: New essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology (pp. 157–172). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, F. (1995/1902). The life of Charles Darwin. London: Senate.

  • Dawkins, R. (2006/1986). The Blind Watchmaker. London: Penguin Books.

  • Depew, D. (2008). Consequence etiology and biological teleology in Aristotle and Darwin. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39, 379–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, E. M. (2001). Cognitive and contextual factors in the emergence of diverse belief systems: Creation versus evolution. Cognitive Psychology, 42, 217–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, E. M. (2008). Conceptual change and evolutionary biology: A developmental analysis. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.), International handbook of research on conceptual change (pp. 263–294). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, E. M., Spiegel, A., Gram, W., Frazier, B. F., Tare, M., Thompson, S., et al. (2010). A conceptual guide to natural history museum visitors’ understanding of evolution. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 47, 326–353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma, D. (2005). Evolution. Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1994). A modern history theory of functions. Noûs, 28(3), 344–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Vrba, E. S. (1982). Exaptation—a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology, 8(1), 4–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, A. J. F., Gelbart, W. M., Miller, J. H., & Lewontin, R. C. (1999). Modern genetic analysis. New York: WH Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. (2011). Children’s intuitive teleology: How the philosophy of science may inform conceptual development research. Paper presented at the 11th International history philosophy and science teaching conference, Thessaloniki, Greece.

  • Kampourakis, K., & Zogza, V. (2007). Students’ preconceptions about evolution: How accurate is the characterization as “Lamarckian” when considering the history of evolutionary thought? Science & Education, 16(3–5), 393–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., & Zogza, V. (2008). Students’ intuitive explanations of the causes of homologies and adaptations. Science & Education, 17(1), 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., & Zogza, V. (2009). Preliminary evolutionary explanations: A basic framework for conceptual change and explanatory coherence in evolution. Science & Education, 18(10), 1313–1340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., Pavlidi, V., Papadopoulou, M. & Palaiokrassa E. (2011). Children’s teleological intuitions: What kind of explanations do 7–8 year olds give for the features of organisms, artifacts and natural objects? Research in Science Education (online first article).

  • Keil, F. C. (1992). The origins of an autonomous biology. In M. R. Gunnar & M. Maratsos (Eds.), Modularity and constraints in language and cognition. Minnesota symposium on child psychology (Vol. 25, pp. 103–138). New Jersey, Erlbaum: Hillsdale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D. (1999). The scope of teleological thinking in preschool children. Cognition, 70, 241–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D. (2003). British and American children’s preferences for teleo-functional explanations of the natural world. Cognition, 88, 201–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D. (2004). Are children “intuitive theists”? reasoning about purpose and design in nature. Psychological Science, 15(5), 295–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelemen, D., & DiYanni, C. (2005). Intuitions about origins: Purpose and intelligent design in children’s reasoning about nature. Journal of Cognition and Development, 6(1), 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). Function and design. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18, 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder, G. V., Leroi, A. M., & Rose, M. R. (1993). Adaptations and history. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 8(8), 294–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2007). Adaptation. In D. L. Hull & M. Ruse (Eds.), Cambridge companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 1–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, R. (2005). Human evolution: An illustrated introduction. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (2001). The triple helix: gene, organism and environment. Cambridge, MA and London, England: Harvard University Press.

  • Mader, S. S. (2004). Biology (8th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (2002). What evolution is. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. R., & Levine, J. (2004). Biology. Upper Sadle River, New Jersey: Prentice Hall Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nehm, R. H., Kim, S. Y., & Sheppard, K. (2010). Academic preparation in biology and advocacy for teaching evolution: Biology versus non-biology teachers. Science Education, 93, 1122–1146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paley, W. (2006/1802). Natural theology or evidence of the existence and attributes of the deity, collected from the appearances of nature. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Purves, W. K., Sadava, D., Orians, G. H., & Heller, C. (2004). Life: The science of biology (7th ed.). New York: WH Freeman & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raven, P. H., Johnson, G. B., Losos, J. B., Mason, K. A., & Singer, S. R. (2008). Biology (8th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, H. K., & Sherman, P. W. (1993). Adaptation and the goals of evolutionary research. Quarterly Review of Biology, 68(1), 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (2004). Evolution (3rd ed.). London: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. U. (2010). Current status of research in teaching and learning evolution: II. Pedagogical issues. Science & Education, 19(6–8), 539–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1993/1984). The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Southerland, S. A., Abrams, E., Cummins, C. L., & Anselmo, J. (2001). Understanding students’ explanations of biological phenomena: Conceptual frameworks or p-prims? Science Education, 85, 328–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and death: An introduction to the philosophy of biology. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. S. (2007). The tinkerer’s accomplice: How design emerges from life itself. Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, England: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2008). Teleology. In M. Ruse (Ed.), The oxford handbook of philosophy of biology (pp. 113–137). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (1992). Adaptation: Current usages. In E. F. Keller & E. A. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology (pp. 13–18). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1996/1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

  • Williams, G. C. (2001/1996). Plan and purpose in nature: The limits of darwinian evolution. London: Phoenix.

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. Philosophical Review, 82(2), 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Patrick Forber and five diligent reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kostas Kampourakis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kampourakis, K. Teaching About Adaptation: Why Evolutionary History Matters. Sci & Educ 22, 173–188 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9363-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-011-9363-2

Keywords

Navigation