Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Neo-Aristotelian Social Justice: An Unanswered Question

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I assess the possibility of advancing a modern conception of social justice under neo-Aristotelian lights, focussing primarily on conceptions that assert a fundamental connection between social justice and eudaimonia. After some preliminary remarks on the extent to which a neo-Aristotelian account must stay close to Aristotle’s own, I focus on Martha Nussbaum’s sophisticated neo-Aristotelian approach, which I argue implausibly overworks the aspects of Aristotle’s thought it appeals to. I then outline the shape of a deeper and more general, and as yet unanswered, problem facing neo-Aristotelian accounts: how to justify the claim that the point of a just society is to assist or enable its members to flourish.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For excellent accounts of Aristotle’s own view can be found in (Annas 1996) and (Barnes 1990).

  2. See also NE 1142a8. I have used the revised translation by Hugh Tredennick: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, and Ernest Barker’s translation: Aristotle, Politics.

  3. It need not be virtuous agents either: witness Alasdair MacIntyre’s vision (MacIntyre 1999) of virtuous character writ large on communities of ‘reliable others’.

  4. Aristotle gives no clear indication how extensive the deficiency is: e.g. NE 1137b; 1141b23–29. Compare (Schofield 2006, p. 319).

  5. See also the direct appeals to globally held intuition at (Nussbaum 2006, p. 70, p. 78, and passim). See also (Nussbaum 1993, pp. 260–265), where Nussbaum moves straight from reflections on the grounds for intelligible interpretation of different cultural and ethical outlooks to the claim that there is some settled agreement about morally salient features of human beings.

  6. For more detail see (Prinz 2009); (Jackson 2011); (Wiredu 1996); and—relatedly, on disagreement over interpretations of nature—(Descola 1996).

  7. The late Tony Judt describes this strand of liberalism as follows: ‘liberalism… is necessarily indeterminate. It is not about some sort of liberal project for society; it is about a society in which the messiness and openness of politics precludes the application of large-scale projects, however rational and ideal—especially, indeed, if they are rational and ideal’ (Judt 2011, p. 315).

References

  • Annas, Julia. 1996. Aristotle on human nature and political virtue. Review of Metaphysics 49: 731–753.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1988. The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1976. Nicomachean ethics (trans: Thomson, J.A.K.), revised Hugh Tredennick. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • Aristotle. 1995. Politics (trans: Ernest Barker). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Barnes, Jonathan. 1990. Aristotle and political liberty. In Aristoteles’ politik, ed. Gunter Patzig, 250–264. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descola, Phillipe. 1996. Constructing natures. In Nature and society, ed. Phillipe Descola, and Gisli Palsson, 82–102. London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, John. 2001. The cunning of unreason. London: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, John. 1980. Natural law and natural rights. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, Philippa. 2001. Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The interpretation of cultures. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, Clifford. 1983. Local knowledge. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, John. 2009. Human nature, personhood, and ethical naturalism. Philosophy 84: 413–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, John. 2012. Ethical naturalism and the constitution of agency. Journal of Value Inquiry 46: 13–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hope, Simon. 2010. The circumstances of justice. Hume Studies 36: 125–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hope, Simon. 2011. Common humanity as a justification for human rights claims. In The philosophy of human rights, ed. G. Ernst, and J.-C. Heilinger, 211–230. Berlin: De Grutyer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1991. After Hume’s justice. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91: 229–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, Rosalind. 2004. On the grounding of the virtues in human nature. In Was ist das fur den menschen gute?, ed. Jan Szaif, 263–275. Berlin: De Grutyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Michael. 2011. Life within limits. Durham NC: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Judt, Tony. 2011. Past imperfect. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, Gavin. 2006. Human good and human function. In The blackwells companion to Aristotle’s nicomachean ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 37–75. London: Blackwells.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1985. After virtue, 2nd ed. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1999. Social structures and their threats to moral agency. Philosophy 74: 311–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1994. Mind and world. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1995. Two sorts of naturalism. In Virtues and reasons, ed. Rosalind Hursthouse, Gavin Lawrence, and Warren Quinn, 149–179. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller Jr, F.D. 1995. Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle’s politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1993. Non-relative virtues. In The quality of life, ed. A. Sen, and Martha Nussbaum, 242–269. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2000. Women and human development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2002. Aristotelian social democracy, revised edition. In Aristotle and modern politics, ed. A. Tessitore, 47–101. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of justice. Cambridge MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, Onora. 1996. Towards justice and virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, Onora. 2001. Practical principles, practical judgment. The Hastings Centre Report 31: 15–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, Jesse. 2009. Against moral nativism. In Stich and his critics, ed. Dominic Murphy, and Michael Bishop, 167–189. Oxford: Blackwells.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, Douglas, and Douglas Den Uyl. 1991. Liberty and nature. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, Malcolm. 1999. Saving the city. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, Malcolm. 2006. Aristotle’s political ethics. In The blackwell’s guide to Aristotle’s nicomachean ethics, ed. Richard Kraut, 305–322. London: Blackwells.

    Google Scholar 

  • Striker, Gisela. 1990. Comments on Irwin. In Aristoteles’ politik, ed. Gunther Patzig, 98–100. Gottingen: Vandenhoek and Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Allen. 2007. Reconciling themes in neo-Aristotelian meta-ethics. The Journal of Value Inquiry 41: 245–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Michael. 1995. The representation of life. In Virtues and reasons, ed. Rosalind Hursthouse, Gavin Lawrence, and Warren Quinn, 247–296. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Michael. 2006. What is it to wrong someone? In Reason and value, ed. R.J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, and M. Smith, 333–384. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toner, Christopher. 2008. Sorts of naturalism: requirements for a successful theory. Metaphilosophy 39: 220–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogler, Candace. 2006. Modern moral philosophy again. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106: 347–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2002. God, Locke, and equality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wall, Stephen. 1998. Liberalism, perfectionism, and restraint. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, David. 2004. Neo-Aristotelian reflections on social justice. Mind 113: 477–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1980. Justice as a virtue. In Essays on Aristotle’s ethics, ed. A.O. Rorty, 189–199. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, Kwasi. 1996. Cultural universals and particulars: An African perspective. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Onora O’Neill, Rosalind Hursthouse, Adrian Haddock, and the late Amanda Perreau-Saussine, for helpful discussions on this topic over many years.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simon Hope.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hope, S. Neo-Aristotelian Social Justice: An Unanswered Question. Res Publica 19, 157–172 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-013-9213-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-013-9213-y

Keywords

Navigation