Skip to main content
Log in

The nature of faith in analytic theistic philosophy of religion

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article I shall analyse and evaluate analytic theists’ views of what it takes to be a person of faith. I suggest that the subject can be approached by posing requirements a person must allegedly fulfil in order to count as a person of faith. These requirements can be referred to as aspects of faith. According to my analysis, four different aspects of faith can be distinguished: the cognitive, the evaluative-affective, the practical, and the interpersonal. There have been divergent assessments about which aspects are indispensable for faith and how they should be understood.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As far as I know, the only even slightly similar treatment to the one at hand is Bishop (2010). However, the scope of Bishop’s description is broader than mine and my analysis diverges from that of Bishop, as I shall point out in the last section of this paper. For different analytically oriented approaches to the nature of faith see e.g. Audi (2011), Lad Sessions (1994) and Yandell (1990).

  2. Audi (2011, pp. 53–54) has distinguished seven different concepts of faith which he thinks the discourse of everyday life contains: “(1) propositional faith, indicated where someone is said to have faith that something is so, (2) attitudinal faith, designated where a person is said to have faith in some being (or other entity, such as an institution), (3) creedal faith, that is, a set of tenets designated by ‘a religious faith’, the kind of faith one belongs to by virtue of commitment to at least its central tenets, (4) global faith, the kind whose possession makes one a person of faith and can qualify one as religious provided that the content of the faith is appropriate, (5) doxastic faith, illustrated by believing something ‘on faith’ (or, perhaps not quite equivalently, ‘in faith’), so we may conceive doxastic faith as one kind of propositional faith, (6) acceptant faith, referred to when someone is said to accept another person, or claimed proposition or proposed action, ‘in good faith’ or, sometimes, ‘on faith’, and (7) what we might call allegiant faith (or loyalty faith), which is roughly fidelity, as exemplified by keeping faith with someone.” For further discussion on these locutions see Audi (2011, pp. 54–62). The notion of faith we are interested in is roughly equivalent to Audi’s global faith. One might note that this concept is close to fides qua creditur, which is contrasted with fides quae creditur. The latter approximates to Audi’s creedal faith.

  3. According to the Thomist tradition, the proposition that there is a God is not, strictly speaking, part of the propositional content of faith but a preamble of it. For it was argued that God’s existence can be known by rational enquiry without special revelation, but the proper content of faith is not knowable in such a way. Instead, the content is specially revealed by God through different mediums (say, Christ, the Bible, or the Church) and concerns God’s nature and the acts he has done. See e.g. Kenny (1983, pp. 69–70, 74–75), Swinburne (2005, p. 138).

  4. It should be stressed, as Audi (2011, p. 62) notes, that the term “acceptance” can be used as an equivalent of “belief”. However, in recent discussion a sharp distinction has been drawn between these attitudes. See e.g. Cohen (1992), Engel ed. (2000).

  5. Swinburne (2005, p. 228) puts this point as follows: “If you insist that, to be a Christian, someone must believe that the creed as a whole is more probable than its negation, it is as though you are telling someone who needs a fortune, and wishes to buy a lottery ticket in the hope of getting it, that he is only allowed to buy the ticket if he believes that the odds are in favour of the ticket winning. That seems unreasonable”.

  6. For example, suppose S estimates that P(p) = 0.4, P(q) = 0.3, and P(r) = 0.3. Here S weakly believes that p against q and r, since P(p) > P(q) and P(p) > P(r), but S does not strongly believe that p, since P(p) < P(not-p).

  7. I leave it open whether a person who is agnostic about the possibility of God’s existence could have faith of a realist kind. One might note that the question of the possibility of God’s existence pertains to the epistemology of modality and is by no means a trivial issue. On modal epistemology see e.g. Vaidya (2015).

  8. Plantinga (2000, p. 291) offers an interesting suggestion according to which the demons might not after all have the relevant beliefs: “The content of faith is plausibly indexical: a person x has faith if x believes or knows that God is benevolent toward x herself. But perhaps the devils do not believe that God is benevolent toward them. They know that God is all-powerful, all-knowing, and perfectly good, and that he has arranged a way of salvation for human beings; but perhaps they reject the belief that God is benevolent toward them”.

  9. Here is what Plantinga says in one connection: “Chief among these right affections is love of God—desire for God, desire to know him, to have a personal relationship with him, desire to achieve a certain kind of unity with him, as well as delight in him, relishing his beauty, greatness, holiness, and the like. There is also trust, approval, gratitude, intending to please, expecting good things, and much more” (Plantinga 2000, p. 292).

  10. According to J. P. Day, Kant emphasized hoping: the postulates of practical are something one hopes for. See Day (1991, pp. 39–42).

  11. One remark relating to the issue at hand may be worth of notice: on the face of it, it is tempting to ask whether “belief in x” and similar expressions “trust in x” and “faith in x” require “belief that x exists”—or, for that matter, “faith that x exists” or “trust that x exists”. I do not wish to settle this issue here. My concern is just to point out that unless one clearly explicates what one means by “belief/faith/trust in”, it is pointless to consider whether they call for “belief/faith/trust that”. For example, while it is prima facie queer to claim “I trust in God but I do not believe that God exists” (cf. Helm 2000, p. 149), according to Swinburne’s analysis of trust there is nothing absurd in this claim. In Swinburne’s view to trust God is, roughly, to act on the assumption that God will do for you what you want or need, and he rightly maintains that such conduct is feasible with mere assumption that there is a God. So, in Swinburne’s view one need not (strongly) believe that God exists in order to trust God (Swinburne 2005, p. 144, 147).

  12. Helm’s distinction between having thin and thick beliefs about God is rather extensive. For further elucidation see Helm (2000, pp. 103–111).

  13. I am inclined to think that one should not build too much into this “feeling” belief allegedly involves, though some seem to do that and though the term appears to be a typical choice of words to describe the phenomenology of belief. Instead of feeling I could equally speak of (involuntarily) seeing or perceiving, for example. For some further discussion see e.g. Eklund (2014, p. 310).

  14. In Bishop’s words, “a theist’s practical commitment involves […] taking it to be true (with full weight) that God exists in his or her practical reasoning; and doing so while holding that God exists (i.e. while having the belief that God exists)” (Bishop 2007, pp. 106–107). Bishop’s “take to be true” and “hold true” correspond to Cohen’s “acceptance” and “belief” respectively. See Bishop (2007, pp. 29–30, 33–41).

  15. As one can see, Kinghorn holds that a personal relationship with God is an authority relation. Moser appears to have a similar conception. See e.g. Moser (2008, pp. 61, 66). Such a link between personal relationship and authority does not hold of necessity in human–human relationships (think about friendships, for example), but it seems to go for divine-human relationships, as God is typically conceived as the ultimate authority. In this connection it may be interesting to note that Kinghorn’s account resembles Bochenski’s analysis of authority. According to Bochenski, authority is a triadic relation A(x, y, g), where x is the authority, y is the subject of authority, and g is the subject matter in which x has authority over y. In Bochenski’s view, y generally accepts g because it is communicated by x. See Bochenski (1974). The similarity of Bochenski’s view to that of Kinghorn is evident: not much would alter in Kinghorn’s view, were he to say that personal relationship with God is a Bochenskian triadic relation A(G, S, invitational statements). For discussion on Bochenski’s view and divine authority, in general, see Knuuttila (2004).

  16. James Beilby has criticized Plantinga’s A/C model of faith on similar grounds. See Beilby (2007, pp. 140–141).

  17. While not taking a stand on such theological questions as whether Christian faith requires membership in the church through baptism, Audi notes that one might think that Christian commitment entirely apart from the church is not full-blooded. But even here Audi seems to hesitate, while at the same time he grants that religious commitment of communal sort may be richer and more supportive than religious commitment which lacks such dimension. See Audi (2011, pp. 96–99).

  18. Bishop notes that “there are also evaluative components in faith—but these may appear as implicated in the affective and/or the cognitive components, according to one's preferred meta-theory of value.” Bishop (2010, Chap. 1). See also Bishop (2007, pp. 103–106).

References

  • Alston, W. (1991). Perceiving God. The epistemology of religious experience. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (1995). Realism and the christian faith. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 38, 37–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (1996). Belief, acceptance, and religious faith. In Jordan & Howard-Snyder (Eds.), Faith, freedom, and rationality (pp. 3–27). Boston: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Alston, W. (2007). Audi on non-doxastic faith. In Timmons et al. (Eds.), Rationality and the good. Critical essays on the ethics and epistemology of Robert Audi (pp. 123–139). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Audi, R. (2011). Rationality and religious commitment. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beilby, J. (2007). Plantinga’s model of warranted christian belief. In D.-P. Baker (Ed.), Alvin Plantinga (pp. 125–165). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, R. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2007). Believing by faith. An essay in the epistemology and ethics of religious belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2010). Faith. In Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2010 edition). Retrieved March 26, 2015 from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/faith/.

  • Cohen, J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Creel, R. (1993). Faith, hope, and faithfulness. Faith and Philosophy, 10(3), 330–344.

  • Day, J. P. (1991). Hope. A philosophical inquiry. Helsinki: Hakapaino Oy.

  • Eklund, D.-J. (2014). Is non-evidential believing possible? John Bishop on passionally caused beliefs. Religious Studies, 50(3), 309–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, P. (Ed.). (2000). Believing and accepting. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golding, J. (1990). Toward a pragmatic conception of religious faith. Faith and Philosophy, 7(4), 486–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, P. (2000). Faith with reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, D. (2013). Propositional faith: What it is and what it is not. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(4), 357–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, J. (2006). Pascal’s wager. Pragmatic arguments and belief in God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1983). Faith and reason. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinghorn, K. (2005). The decision of faith: Can christian beliefs be freely chosen?. New York: T & T Clark International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, S. (2004). Biblical authority and philosophy. In D. Z. Phillips & M. von der Ruhr (Eds.), Biblical concepts and our world (pp. 113–127). Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Koistinen, T. (2000). Philosophy of religion or religious philosophy? A critical study of contemporary anglo-american approaches. Helsinki: Luthe-Agricola-Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lad Session, W. (1993). The certainty of faith. In Radcliffe & White (Eds.), Faith in theory and practice. Essays on justifying religious belief (pp. 75–89). Chicago: Open Court.

  • Lad Sessions, W. (1994). The concept of faith. A philosophical investigation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Moser, P. (2008). The elusive God. Reorienting religious epistemology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. (2010). The evidence for God. Religious knowledge reexamined. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. (2013). The severity of God. Religion and philosophy reconceived. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Muyskens, J. (1979). The sufficiency of hope. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penelhum, T. (2013). Religion after atheism. Religious Studies, 49(2), 249–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1983). Reason and belief in God. In Plantinga & Wolterstorff (Eds.), Faith and rationality. Reason and belief in God (pp. 16–93). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted christian belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pojman, L. (1986). Religious belief and the will. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pojman, L. (2003). Faith, doubt and hope or does faith entail belief? In Gale & Pruss (Eds.), The existence of God (pp. 535–549). Wilsthire: The Cromwell Press.

  • Price, H. H. (1969). Belief. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radcliffe, D. (1995). Non-doxastic faith. Audi on religious commitment. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 37(2), 73–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. L. (2005). Prolegomena to a philosophy of religion. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1993). The coherence of theism (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2001). Plantinga on warrant. Religious Studies, 37(2), 203–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2005). Faith and reason (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vahid, H. (2009). Alston on belief and acceptance in religious faith. The Heythrop Journal, 50(1), 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaidya, A. (2015). The epistemology of modality. In Zalta (Ed.) forthcoming, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2015 edition). Retrieved April 23, 2015 from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/modality-epistemology/.

  • Yandell, K. (1990). The nature of faith: Religious, monotheistic, and christian. Faith and Philosophy, 7(4), 451–469.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dan-Johan Eklund.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eklund, DJ. The nature of faith in analytic theistic philosophy of religion. Int J Philos Relig 80, 85–99 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9545-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9545-y

Keywords

Navigation