Skip to main content
Log in

Does absence make atheistic belief grow stronger?

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Discussion of the role which religious experience can play in warranting theistic belief has received a great deal of attention within contemporary philosophy of religion. By contrast, the relationship between experience and atheistic belief has received relatively little focus. Our aim in this paper is to begin to remedy that neglect. In particular, we focus on the hitherto under-discussed question of whether experiences of God’s absence can provide positive epistemic status for a belief in God’s nonexistence. We argue that there is good reason to accept an epistemic parity between experiences of God’s presence and experiences of God’s absence

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We consider one reason for denying this in “Evaluating the new approach” below, but since this reason entails denying Martin’s conditional claim, it cannot be deployed in defence of his argument.

  2. See e.g. Schellenberg (1993) and Murray (1993).

  3. We will talk in what follows as if absences can serve as genuine causal relata but our account is compatible with rejecting this view in favour of one in which they are merely able to feature in true causal explanations (in Beebee’s (2004, p. 293) sense).

  4. Rea himself merely reports this claim without endorsing it.

  5. This is not, of course, to claim that we might not have other reasons to disregard their testimony (perhaps the sailors in question have a penchant for rum or a history of making up tales of fantastical creatures).

  6. For defences of this claim see e.g. Goldman (1979) and Chisholm (1989).

  7. See Chap. 5.3 of Reid (1764/2011).

  8. Plantinga doesn’t call the relevant circumstances ‘signs’, but we will use this term to include both Evans-style TNSs and the stimuli which Plantinga claims may trigger the sensus divinitatis.

  9. See, e.g., Camus’ The Myth of Sisyphus for one famous example.

  10. Strictly speaking, the universe itself—considered as a spatiotemporal object—would be indifferent, but, given the dictates of divine providence it would not function in an indifferent manner.

  11. Technically, the counterfactual link here is not with the non-existence of the God of classical theism in particular, but with the non-existence of any kind of supernatural being capable of, e.g., enforcing order on the universe. We will, however, ignore this complication in what follows.

  12. See Lewis (1973) and Stalnaker (1968).

  13. While these accounts are explicitly formulated in terms of information and signalling respectively, the insights they offer can easily be incorporated into an account of signs.

  14. For Plantinga’s famous argument against combining atheism (or, rather, naturalism) with a proper function account see his (Plantinga 1993, pp. 194–238). For responses see e.g. Fitelson and Sober (2003).

  15. Indeed, most contemporary accounts of the nature of function make no appeal to intentions (see Millikan (1998) for an extremely influential account of this kind).

  16. By which we mean merely that they successfully function so as to produce true belief. Again, see Millikan (1998) for an account of this kind.

  17. Indeed Evans himself makes this kind of suggestion when he says ‘an atheistic Reidian would presumably have to see the link between the sign and what is signified in perception as non-accidental, perhaps seeing the link as one that has some functional value that has provided an evolutionary edge.’ (2010, p. 36).

  18. See, e.g., Murray (1993).

  19. We would like to thank the audience at the University of Nottingham workshop on religious experience, an anonymous referee for the journal, and a different token of one of this paper's authors for their useful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

References

  • Alston, W. (1991). Perceiving God: The epistemology of religious experience. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. (1274/1978). Summa Theologica, Raleigh: Hayes Barton Press.

  • Beebee, H. (2004). Causing and nothingness. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 291–308). London: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1989). Theory of knowledge (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Meskin, A. (2006). An objective counterfactual theory of information. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(3), 333–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (2010). Natural signs and knowledge of God: A new look at theistic arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Farennikova, A. (2013). Seeing absence. Philosophical Studies, 166, 429–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B., & Sober, E. (2003). Plantinga’s probability arguments against evolutionary naturalism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79(2), 115–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1979). What is Justified Belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 1–23). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (1982). Religious belief and religious skepticism. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1941). Man’s vision of God and the logic of theism. New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748/1975). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kwan, K. (2006). ‘Can religious experience provide justification for the belief in God? The debate in contemporary analytic philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 1(6), 640–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1986). The principle of credulity and religious experience. Religious Studies, 22(1), 79–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1990). Atheism: A philosophical justification. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mawson, T. J. (2005). Belief in God. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1998). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56(2), 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M. (1993). Coercion and the hiddenness of God. American Philosophical Quarterly, 30(1), 27–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, B. (1995). Pensées and other writings, (tr. Honor Levi). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1981). Is belief in God properly basic? Noûs, 15, 41–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted christian belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (2011). Divine hiddenness, divine silence. In L. Pojman & M. Rea (Eds.), Philosophy of religion: An anthology (6th ed., pp. 266–275). Boston: Wadsworth/Cengage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. (1764/2011). An inquiry into the human mind, on the principles of common sense. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Reid, T. (1785/2002). Essays on the intellectual powers of man, In D. R. Brookes (ed.), Bodmin: Edinburgh University Press.

  • Schellenberg, J. L. (1993). Divine hiddenness and human reason. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (2008). Seeing dark things: The philosophy of shadows. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, C. L. (2001). When is it selectively advantageous to have true beliefs? Sandwiching the better safe than sorry argument. Philosophical Studies, 105(2), 161–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1977). The coherence of theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1979). The existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jon Robson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Adams, S., Robson, J. Does absence make atheistic belief grow stronger?. Int J Philos Relig 79, 49–68 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9532-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-015-9532-3

Keywords

Navigation