Skip to main content
Log in

On the efficiency of equilibria in a legislative bargaining model with particularistic and collective goods

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This study analyzes the efficiency of equilibria in a multilateral bargaining game in which a legislature divides its budget among collective and particularistic goods. In order to disentangle the causes of inefficiency, we extend the model of Volden and Wiseman (Am Polit Sci Rev 101:79–92, 2007) by considering quasi-linear utility functions, and consensus requirements ranging from simple majority to unanimity. Although unanimous agreements can be reached under weaker consensus requirements, we show that (Pareto) inefficiency is associated with non-unanimous consent. We also study how (i) the endogenous selection of the legislature’s size or (ii) a sequential choice of collective and particularistic spending eliminates or attenuates the inefficiency problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Volden and Wiseman (2008) where some previous errors are corrected.

  2. Quasi-linearity is commonly used when collective decisions involve costly collective spending. Although some degree of complementarity between collective and private goods is reasonable, quasi-linearity allows us to represent the preferences of the legislators over allocations that are independent of any income effect. As such, it effectively simplifies the analysis. Alternatively, quasi-linearity can also be re-interpreted as a setting with linear preferences in which the transformation process of public spending into a consumable public good is not linear.

  3. A different approach studies the effects of majoritarian regimes on the stability of collective outcomes (see, e.g., Greenberg 1979; Caplin and Nalebuff 1988; Austen-Smith and Banks 1999a, b), or the stability of legislative rules themselves (see Barberà and Jackson 2004).

  4. This result is in line with Riker’s (1962) prediction that a minimal coalition would determine the collective choice.

  5. Fréchette et al. (2012) study VW’s model and show that some of their qualitative results (specifically those related to proposers exploiting the impatience of others) are not supported experimentally. This suggests that both VW and our model overlook some behavioral aspects regarding the way in which agents may exploit the impatience of others in the negotiation process. Nevertheless, most of our analysis considers almost patient players, and focuses on how bargaining equilibria are affected by both the consensus requirement and the size of the legislature.

  6. Indeed, under complete depreciation of investments (that is, public good spending) efficiency would never be attained if the valuation of the public good is high with respect to the particularistic good, even under unanimity.

  7. Adopting a different approach, Battaglini et al. (2014) study a model where agents simultaneously and independently decide what fractions of their budget to invest in a durable public good. The paper compares the equilibria in the game where agents can disinvest with the equilibria in the game where agents cannot transform past contributions into current consumption.

  8. The role of α and β in VW (\(u_{j}\left( {\mathbf {x}}\right) =\alpha x_{j}+\beta y\)) differs from present model. However, the two parameters have the same qualitative interpretation in both models.

  9. As Eraslan (2002) points out, in non-unanimous bargaining games, the uniqueness of SSPE expected outcomes does not imply a unique SSPE. As all minimal winning coalitions have the same cost for the proposer, there are many SSPE where all responders have the same probability of being included in a winning coalition.

  10. This contrasts with VW’s linear model where, after reducing impatience (or transaction costs) to the limit, inefficiencies arise only for intermediate values of the relative valuation of particularistic goods.

  11. As proposals are unanimously accepted when \(\alpha \in [\alpha_{1},\alpha_{2}),\) it may be thought that the winning coalition size q has no effect on the equilibrium outcome. However, this is not correct exactly, since \(\alpha_{2}\) depends on q.

  12. Christiansen (2013) also considers the possibility that the members of the legislature alter its original structure. He studies the effects of strategic delegation by legislature members when preferences are heterogenous.

  13. If \(N<32,\) the legislature’s size will increase to \(n_{f}=N\) only if \(u\left( n_{o}\right) \le u\left( N\right).\)

  14. If \(N<\alpha /Q\beta\) the equilibrium provision of collective good of any stable legislature is Pareto efficient, except when \(n_{o}\in \left[ \alpha /\beta ,\alpha /Q\beta \right).\) In this case, legislators would like to increase the size of the legislature only beyond N. Therefore, the legislature is stable because the population size is binding. Within this legislature size range, the equilibrium collective good provision is inefficient (under-provision).

  15. Notice that the situation wherein legislators first negotiate private spending is equivalent to the baseline model.

References

  • Aghion, P., & Bolton, P. (2003). Incomplete social contracts. Journal of the European Economics Association, 1, 38–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D., & Banks, J. S. (1988). Elections, coalitions, and legislative outcomes. American Political Science Review, 82, 409–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D., & Banks, J. S. (1999a). Positive political theory I. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D., & Banks, J. S. (1999b). Cycling of simple rules in the spatial model. Social Choice and Welfare, 16(4), 663–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banks, J. S., & Duggan, J. (2000). A bargaining model of collective choice. American Political Science Review, 94, 73–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banks, J. S., & Duggan, J. (2006). A general bargaining model of legislative policy-making. Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 1, 49–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà, S. & Jackson, M.O. (2004). Choosing how to choose: Self-stable majority rules and constitutions. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 119(3), 1011–1048.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, D., & Ferejohn, J. (1989). Bargaining in legislatures. American Political Science Review, 83, 1181–1206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, D., & Diermeier, D. (2001). Elections, governments, and parliaments in proportional representation systems. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116, 933–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battaglini, M., Nunnari, S., & Palfrey, T. (2014). Dynamic free riding with irreversible investments. American Economic Review (forthcoming).

  • Battaglini, M., Nunnari, S., & Palfrey, T. (2012). Legislative bargaining and the dynamics of public investment. American Political Science Review, 106(2), 407–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besley, T., & Coate, S. (1998). Sources of inefficiency in a representative democracy: A dynamic analysis. American Economic Review, 88(1), 139–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bond, P., & Eraslan, H. (2010). Strategic voting over strategic proposals. The Review of Economic Studies, 77(2), 459–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplin, A., & Nalebuff, B. (1988). On the 64 %-majority rule. Econometrica, 56, 787–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardona, D., & Ponsatí, C. (2011). Uniqueness of stationary equilibria in bargaining one-dimensional policies under (super) majority rules. Games and Economic Behavior, 73, 65–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardona, D. & Ponsatí, C. (2014). Super-majorities, one-dimensional policies, and social surplus. Journal of Public Economic Theory (forthcoming).

  • Christiansen, N. (2013). Strategic delegation in a legislative bargaining model with pork and public goods. Journal of Public Economics, 97, 217–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (2012). The political economy of Gordon Tullock. Public Choice, 121, 213–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, G. (1987). Electoral equilibria under alternative voting institutions. American Journal of Political Science, 31(1), 82–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crombez, C. (1996). Minority governments, minimal winning coalitions and budget majorities in parliamentary systems. European Journal of Political Research, 29, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fréchette, G. R., Kagel, J. H., & Morelli, M. (2012). Pork versus public goods: An experimental study of public good provision within a legislative bargaining. Economic Theory, 49, 779–800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eraslan, H. (2002). Uniqueness of stationary equilibrium payoff in the Baron-Ferejohn model. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 11–30.

  • Greenberg, J. (1979). Consistent majority rules over compact sets of alternatives. Econometrica, 47(3), 627–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harstad, B. (2005). Majority rules and incentives. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 120(4), 1535–1568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harstad, B. (2010). Strategic delegation and voting rules. Journal of Public Economics, 94, 102–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holden, R.T. (2009). Supermajority voting rules, unpublished work.

  • Jackson, M. O., & Moselle, B. (2002). Coalition and party formation in a legislative voting game. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 49–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leblanc, W., Snyder, J. M, Jr, & Tripathi, M. (2000). Majority-rule bargaining and the under provision of public investment goods. Journal of Public Economics, 75, 21–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lizzeri, A., & Persico, N. (2011). The provision of public goods under alternative electoral incentives. American Economic Review, 91(1), 225–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (1999). The size and scope of government: Comparative politics with rational politicians. European Economic Review, 43, 699–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1962). The theory of political coalitions. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volden, C., & Wiseman, A. E. (2007). Bargaining in legislatures over particularistic and collective goods. American Political Science Review, 101, 79–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volden, C., & Wiseman, A. E. (2008). Erratum to “Bargaining in legislatures over particularistic and collective goods”. American Political Science Review, 102, 385–386.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We acknowledge financial support from the Generalitat de Catalunya through Grant SGR2009-1051 and Ministerio de Ciencia y Tecnologia through Grants ECO2012-34046 and ECO2011-23934. We are also grateful for the suggestions of the editor, the associate editor and two anonymous referees that have improved the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antoni Rubí-Barceló.

Appendices

Appendix

Proofs

Proof (Proof of Lemma 2)

Let \({\overline{u}_{1}}\le \cdots \le {\overline{u}_{q}}\le \cdots \le {\overline{u}_{n}}\) with some strict inequality. Using the no-delay property of the SSPE, expected utilities are given by

$$\begin{aligned} n{\overline{u}_{1}}&= \delta \left[{\sum \nolimits_{i\notin \left\{ 1,n\right\} }} {\overline{u}_{1}^i}+{\overline{u}_{1}^1}+{\overline{u}_{1}^n}\right] \\ n{\overline{u}_{n}}&=\delta \left[ {\sum\nolimits_{i\notin \left\{ 1,n\right\} }} {\overline{u}_{n}^i}+{\overline{u}_{n}^1}+{\overline{u}_{n}^n}\right] \end{aligned}$$

where \({\overline{u}_{j}}^{i}\) denotes the expected utility obtained by player \(j\) when \(i\) is the proposer.

Since the cheapest to assemble winning coalition is chosen by any proposer \(i \notin \{1,n\}\), then \(u_{1}^{i}\ge \delta {\overline{u}_{1}}\) if \(u_{n}^{i}=\delta {\overline{u}_{n}}\) and \(u_{1}^{i}\ge u_{n}^{i}\) otherwise. Thus,

$$n\left[ {\overline{u}_{n}}-{\overline{u}_{1}}\right] \le m\delta \left[ {\overline{u}_{n}}-{\overline{u}_{1}}\right] +\delta \left[ {\overline{u}_{n}^1}+{\overline{u}_{n}^n}-{\overline{u}_{1}^1}-{\overline{u}_{1}^n}\right]$$

for some \(m\in \left[ 0,n-2\right]\).

Moreover, either \(u_{1}^{n}\ge \delta {\overline{u}_{1}}\) and \(u_{n}^{1} \le \delta {\overline{u}_{n}}\) or \(1\) is not included in the cheapest to assemble winning coalition. In the last case, the optimal proposal of agent \(1\) is also \({\mathbf x^{n}}\) so that \({\overline{u}_{1}^1} = {\overline{u}_{n}^n}\) and \({\overline{u}_{1}}^{n} = {\overline{u}_{n}^1}\) . Thus,

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ n-m\delta \right] \left[ {\overline{u}_{n}}-{\overline{u}_{1}}\right] \le 0\text {,} \end{aligned}$$

which is a contradiction.

In case that \(u_{1}^{n}\ge \delta {\overline{u}_{1}}\) and \(u_{n}^{1}\le \delta \overline{u}_{n}\) we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ n-\left( m+1\right) \delta \right] \left[ \overline{u} _{n}-\overline{u}_{1}\right] \le \delta \left[ \overline{u}_{n}^{n} -\overline{u}_{1}^{1}\right] \text {.} \end{aligned}$$

By mimicking the proposal of agent \(n\) player \(1\) can obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \overline{u}_{1}^{1}\ge \alpha \left( 1-y_{n}-\sum_{i\in L-\{1,n\}} x_{j}^{n}-x_{n}^{1}\right) +y_{n}^{\beta }, \end{aligned}$$

where \(x_{n}^{1}=\max \left\{ \frac{\delta \overline{u}_{n}-y_{n}^{\beta }}{\alpha },0\right\}\). Thus, \(\overline{u}_{n}^{n}-\overline{u}_{1}^{1}=\alpha \left( x_{n}^{1}-x_{1}^{n}\right)\). We distinguish three cases:

  1. 1.

    \(x_{n}^{1}=0\), which implies \(x_{1}^{n}=0\). In this case, we obtain

    $$\begin{aligned} \left[ n-\left( m+1\right) \delta \right] \left[ \overline{u} _{n}-\overline{u}_{1}\right] \le 0\text {,} \end{aligned}$$

    which is a contradiction.

  2. 2.

    \(x_{n}^{1}=\frac{\delta \overline{u}_{n}-y_{n}^{\beta }}{\alpha }\) and \(x_{1}^{n}=0\). Since \(y_{n}^{\beta }\ge \delta \overline{u}_{1}\),

    $$\begin{aligned} \alpha \left( x_{n}^{1}-x_{1}^{n}\right) =\alpha x_{n}^{1}=\delta \overline{u}_{n}-y_{n}^{\beta }\le \delta \left( \overline{u}_{n}-\overline{u}_{1}\right) , \end{aligned}$$

    and therefore

    $$\begin{aligned} \left[ n-\left( m+2\right) \delta \right] \left[ \overline{u} _{n}-\overline{u}_{1}\right] \le 0\text {,} \end{aligned}$$

    which is also a contradiction.

  3. 3.

    Similarly, if \(x_{n}^{1}=\frac{\delta \overline{u}_{n}-y_{n}^{\beta }}{\alpha }\) and \(x_{1}^{n}=\frac{\delta \overline{u}_{1}-y_{1}^{\beta }}{\alpha }\) then \(\alpha \left( x_{n}^{1}-x_{1}^{n}\right) =\delta \left( \overline{u}_{n}-\overline{u} _{1}\right)\) and a contradiction is obtained, too.

\(\square\)

Lemma 4

\(\alpha_{1}=\left[ \frac{n(1-\delta )\beta ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}}{ \delta }+\beta ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\right] ^{1-\beta }\) and \(\alpha _{2} = \left[ {\frac{{n\left( {nQ} \right)^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} (1 - \delta )\beta ^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} }}{\delta } + \left( {nQ} \right)^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} \beta ^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} } \right]^{{1 - \beta }} > \alpha _{1} > \beta .\)

Proof

\(\alpha_{1}\) solves \(f(y_{1},\alpha_{1};\delta )=\frac{\alpha \delta }{n} (1-y_{1})-(1-\delta )y_{1}^{\beta }=0\). That is, \(\frac{\alpha_{1}\delta }{n} (1-y_{1})-(1-\delta )y_{1}^{\beta }=0\). Substituting \(y_{1}\) and rearranging terms, we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha_{1}=\left[ \frac{n(1-\delta )\beta ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}}{\delta }+ \beta ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\right] ^{1-\beta } \end{aligned}$$

Similarly, \(\alpha_{2}\) solves \(f(y_{q},\alpha_{2};\delta )=\frac{\alpha_{2}\delta }{n}(1-y_{q})-(1-\delta )y_{q}^{\beta }=0\) and therefore substituting \(y_{q}=\left( \beta q /\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\) we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha_{2}=\left[ \frac{n(1-\delta )(q\beta ) ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}}{\delta }+ (q\beta ) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\right] ^{1-\beta } \end{aligned}$$

It is immediate to see that \(\alpha_{1}>\beta\) and \(\alpha_{2}>\alpha_{1}\). \(\square\)

Proof (Proof of Proposition 2)

By Proposition 1, \(\alpha_{1}\rightarrow \beta\) and \(\alpha_{2}\rightarrow \beta nQ\) when \(\delta \rightarrow 1\). Thus, in the limiting case (\(\delta \rightarrow 1\)), SSPE proposals given by Proposition 1 can be written as:

  1. (a)

    \(\mathbf {x}^{*}=(0,0,1)\) if \(n>n^{*}\),

  2. (b)

    \(\mathbf {x}^{*}=(1-(q-1)x-y_{q},x,y_{q})\) if \(n\le n^{*}\) where \(x=\frac{1}{\alpha }f\left( y_{q},\alpha ;\delta \right)\).

When \(n_{o}\ge n^{*}\) legislators cannot increase their utility by adding new members to the legislature. Thus, \(n_{f}\ge n_{o}\) when \(n_{o}\ge n^{*}\).

When \(n_{o}<n^{*},\, y_{q}=\left( \beta n_{o}Q/\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta } }\) and \(x=\frac{1-\left( \beta n_{o}Q/\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}}{n_{o}}\), thus the legislators’ utility is

$$\begin{aligned} u(n_{o})=\alpha \frac{1-\left( \beta n_{o}Q/\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}}{n_{o}}+\left( \beta n_{o}Q/\alpha \right) ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}. \end{aligned}$$

Let \(W(n)=nu(n)\). Since \(W^{\prime }\left( n\right) >0,\, W^{\prime \prime }\left( n\right) >0,\, W\left( 1\right) >0,\, W\left( n^{*}\right) =n^{*}\), and

$$\begin{aligned} W^{\prime }\left( n^{*}\right) =\frac{1}{1-\beta }\left( \frac{\beta Q}{\alpha }\right) ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}\left[ 1-\beta Q\right] \left( \frac{\alpha }{\beta Q}\right) ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}=\frac{1-\beta Q}{1-\beta }>1, \end{aligned}$$

then \(W\left( n\right) =n\) has exactly one solution \(\widehat{n}<n^{*}\). Notice that a fixed point of \(W\left( n\right)\) holds that \(u(n)=1\). So, by the convexity of \(W\), we have that \(u(n_{o})<1\) only when \(n_{o}\in (\widehat{n},n^{*})\). Moreover, when \(n_{o}<\widehat{n} ,\, u(n_{o})>u\left( n_{f}\right)\) for all \(n_{f}>n_{o}\), so legislators do not have any incentives to accept new members into the legislature. In consequence, only when \(n_{o}\in (\widehat{n},n^{*})\) will the legislators have any incentives to increase the size of their legislature so that \(n_{o}<n_{f}\), where \(n_{f}\ge n^{*}\).

When \(Q=1\), then

$$\begin{aligned} u(n) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l}&1 &\qquad {{\text{if }}n \ge \alpha /\beta } \\&{\alpha \frac{{1 - \left( {\beta n/\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} }}{n} + \left( {\beta n/\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} } &\qquad {{\text{otherwise}}{\text{.}}}\\ \end{array} } \right. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, \(n_{f}\ge n_{o}\) when \(n_{o}\ge \alpha /\beta\) because legislators cannot increase their utility by adding new members to the legislature; when \(n_{o}<\alpha /\beta\) the members of the original legislature will not have any incentives to add new members because \(W^{\prime }\left( n^{*}\right) =1\), implying \(u^{\prime }(n_{o})<0\) (due to the convexity of \(W\)).

Finally, we show that \(\widehat{n}<\alpha /\beta\). This holds if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} u(\alpha /\beta )=\beta \left( 1-Q^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\right) +Q^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}\equiv V(Q)<1. \end{aligned}$$

Since \(V^{\prime }(Q)>0\) and \(V(1)=1\), it can be concluded that \(V(Q)<1\) for any \(Q\in (0,1)\). \(\square\)

Proof (Proof of Proposition 3)

[Proof of Proposition 3]In the linear model of VW, where \(Qn=\left( n+1\right) /2\), three cases can be distinguished in the limiting case (\(\delta \rightarrow 1\)): (1) \(n_{o}\ge \alpha /\beta Q\), (2) \(n_{o}\in \left[ \alpha /\beta ,\alpha /\beta Q\right)\), and (3) \(n_{o}<\alpha /\beta\). In the first case, the efficient and equilibrium provisions of the collective good are both equal to \(1\). Moreover, notice that adding new members to the legislature does not change the utility of the original legislators, so legislatures within this size range are stable. In case (3), the efficient and equilibrium provisions of the collective good are both equal to \(0\) and the expected particularistic share of any legislator is \(1/n_{o}\). Moreover, \(u\left( 0,0,1\right) <u\left( {\hat{\mathbf{x}}}\right)\) where \({\hat{\mathbf{x}} }=\left( 1/n_{o},...,1/n_{o},0\right)\), so that the legislature is stable. In case (2), the equilibrium outcome \(y=0\) is inefficient (under-provision). Within this range, legislators obtain an expected utility \(\alpha /n_{o}\) smaller than \(\beta\), thus they have incentives to add new members to the legislature until the new size is greater or equal to \(\alpha /\beta Q\), where the whole budget will be assigned to the collective good in equilibrium. Hence, this is only possible when \(N\ge \alpha /\beta Q\). If this holds, legislatures are not stable when \(n_{o}\in \left[ \alpha /\beta ,\alpha /\beta Q\right)\). Otherwise, legislatures of size \(n_{o}\in \left[ \alpha /\beta ,\alpha /\beta Q\right)\) are stable and yield inefficient bargaining outcomes. \(\square\)

Endogenous size of the legislature when \(\delta <1\)

Consider the notation introduced in Sect. 4.1, where \(nQ=q\). When \(\delta \rightarrow 1,\, y^{*}\left( n\right) =\min \left\{ 1,\left( \beta Qn/\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\right\}\) whereas Pareto efficiency requires a provision of the collective good of \(y^{0}\left( n\right) =\min \left\{ \left( \beta n/\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }},1\right\}\) . By assuming \(\delta <1\) the collective good provision displays the four elements represented in Proposition 1, which complicates the analysis and makes less clear predictions. Nevertheless, we next specify the conditions required to obtain Pareto improvements by increasing the size of the legislature.

As noted, adding new members to the legislature may mean that they appropriate part of the budget, so the legislators will be willing to incorporate new members only if the resulting provision of the collective good increases. The size of the legislature affects \(\alpha_{1},\, \alpha_{2},\, \widehat{y}\), and \(y^{*}\left( n\right)\) defined in Proposition . Specifically, \(\frac{\partial \alpha_{1}\left( n\right) }{\partial n }>0\), \(\frac{\partial \alpha_{2}\left( n\right) }{\partial n}>0,\, \frac{ \partial \widehat{y}\left( n\right) }{\partial n}<0\) and \(\frac{\partial y^{*}\left( n\right) }{\partial n}\ge 0.\)

Suppose that \(\alpha >\beta,\) so that the provision of the collective good is affected by the (endogenous) size of the legislature. In these cases, the utility of the committee members is given by

$$u\left( n \right) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\alpha \frac{{1 - \left( {\beta /\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} }}{n} + \left( {\beta /\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} } & {{\text{if }}\alpha \le \alpha _{1} \left( n \right)} \\ \alpha \frac{{1 - \hat{y}\left( n \right)}}{n} + \hat{y}^{\beta } \left( n \right) & {\text{if }}\alpha \in \left( {\alpha _{1} \left( n \right),\alpha _{2} \left( n \right)} \right) \hfill\\ \alpha \frac{{1 - \left( {\beta nQ/\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} }}{n} + \left( {\beta nQ/\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} & {\text{otherwise}}{\text{.}} \hfill \\ \\ \end{array} } \right.$$

Since \(\widehat{y}\) is attained whenever \(\alpha \in \left[ \alpha_{1}\left( n\right) ,\alpha_{2}\left( n\right) \right]\) and the collective good is constant when \(\alpha <\alpha_{1}\left( n\right),\) it is immediate to see that the original legislature would never increase its size when \(\alpha \le \alpha_{2}\left( n_{o}\right)\) since any increase in \(n\) can only reduce the provision of the collective good. This is formally stated in the next result.

Lemma 5

For any \(\alpha \le \alpha_{2}\left( n\right) ,\, \partial u\left( n\right) /\partial n<0.\)

Proof

When \(\alpha \le \alpha_{1},\)

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \left( \alpha \dfrac{1-\left( \beta /\alpha \right) ^{\frac{1 }{1-\beta }}}{n}+\left( \beta /\alpha \right) ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta } }\right) }{\partial n}<0 \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, when \(\alpha \in \left( \alpha_{1},\alpha_{2}\right) ,\)

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{{\partial \left( {\alpha \frac{{1 - \hat{y}}}{n} + \hat{y}^{\beta } } \right)}}{{\partial n}} & & & = \alpha \frac{{ - n\frac{{\partial \hat{y}}}{{\partial n}} - \left( {1 - \hat{y}} \right)}}{{n^{2} }} + \beta \hat{y}^{{\beta - 1}} \frac{{\partial \hat{y}}}{{\partial n}} \\ & & & \; = - \frac{{\alpha \left( {1 - \hat{y}} \right)}}{n}\frac{1}{n} + \left[ {\beta \hat{y}^{{\beta - 1}} - \frac{\alpha }{n}} \right]\frac{{\partial \hat{y}}}{{\partial n}} \\ \end{aligned}$$

Since \(\frac{\partial {\widehat{y}}}{\partial n}=-\frac{\alpha \delta (1- {\widehat{y}})}{n\alpha \delta +{n^{2}}\beta (1-\delta ){\widehat{y}}^{\beta -1}},\) after some algebra we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \left( \alpha \dfrac{1-{\widehat{y}}}{n}+{\widehat{y}}^{\beta }\right) }{\partial n} = -\frac{\alpha \left( 1-{\widehat{y}}\right) \beta }{n\alpha \delta +n^{2}\beta (1-\delta ){\widehat{y}}^{\beta -1}}{\widehat{y}}^{\beta -1}<0. \end{aligned}$$

\(\square\)

Although legislatures are stable when \(\alpha \le \alpha_{2}\left( {n_{o}}\right),\) this is not necessarily the case when \(\alpha >\alpha_{2}\left( {n_{o}}\right),\) where increasing the size of the legislature might increase the provision of the collective good. Hence, legislators may be interested in selecting \({n_{f}}>{n_{o}}\) if the individual gains from such an increase outweigh the losses derived from reducing the expected particularistic share of their members.

For any given α, using the definitions of \(\alpha_{1}\left( n\right)\) and \(\alpha_{2}\left( n\right),\) the utility function can be written in terms of the legislature’s size as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} u\left( n \right) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\alpha \frac{{1 - \left( {\beta /\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} }}{n} + \left( {\beta /\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} } & {{\text{if }}n > n_{1} } \\ \alpha \frac{{1 - \hat{y}}}{n} + \hat{y}^{\beta } \hfill & {\text{if }}n \in \left( {n_{2} ,n_{1} } \right) \hfill \\ \alpha \frac{{1 - \left( {\beta nQ/\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{1}{{1 - \beta }}}} }}{n} + \left( {\beta nQ/\alpha } \right)^{{\frac{\beta }{{1 - \beta }}}} \hfill & {\text{otherwise}}{\text{.}} \hfill \\ \\ \end{array} } \right. \end{aligned}$$

where \({n_{1}}=\frac{\delta \left( \alpha ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}-\beta ^{\frac{1 }{1-\beta }}\right) }{(1-\delta )\beta ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}}\) and \({n_{2}}=\frac{\alpha }{\left( Q\beta \right) ^{\beta }}\left( \frac{\delta }{ (1-\delta )+\delta Q\beta }\right) ^{1-\beta}.\)

From Lemma 5, we know that \({u^{\prime} }\left( n\right) <0\) for all \(n>{n_{2}}.\) Thus, the legislature would be willing to add new members only if \({n_{o}}\le {n_{2}}.\) Figure 5 depicts the utility of the legislature’s members as a function of its size for a specific example. In this case, \(u\left( n\right)\) attains a local maximum at \(n={n_{2}}=29.085.\) Thus, there exists a range of values of \({n_{o}}<n_{2}\) where increasing the committee size to \({n_{2}}\) would generate a Pareto improvement. The following lemma states the condition required for this property to hold.

Fig. 5
figure 5

Expected utility of a legislature member as a function of \(n\) when \(\left( \alpha ,\beta ,Q\right) =\left( 8,0.5,0.5\right)\) and \(\delta =0.95.\) The legislature would modify its size when \({n_{o}}\in \left( 11.736,29.085\right).\) Not surprisingly, this range is reduced with respect to the example represented by Fig. 4 in Sect. 4.1 where \({n_{o}}\in \left( 10.667,32\right)\) when \(\delta \rightarrow 1\)

Lemma 6

Given \(Q,\, \alpha\) and β, if \(\delta >{\widetilde{\delta} }=\frac{1-\beta}{ 1-Q\beta}\) then \({\widetilde{n}} \equiv {\mathrm{argmin} }_{n\le n_{2}}u(n)<n_{2}.\)

Proof

When \(n\ge n_{2},\)

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial u(n)}{\partial n}&= \frac{1}{n^{2}\left( 1-\beta \right) } \left( -\alpha +\alpha \beta -\alpha \frac{\beta }{\left( Q\frac{n}{\alpha } \beta \right) ^{\frac{1}{\beta -1}}}+n\frac{\beta }{\left( Q\frac{n}{\alpha } \beta \right) ^{\frac{\beta }{\beta -1}}}\right) \\&= \frac{1}{n^{2}\left( 1-\beta \right) }\left( \alpha ^{-\frac{\beta }{ 1-\beta }}n^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\beta ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}Q^{\frac{\beta }{ 1-\beta }}\left[ 1-Q\beta \right] -\alpha \left( 1-\beta \right) \right) , \end{aligned}$$

which equals zero if

$$\begin{aligned} n^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}&= \frac{\alpha \left( 1-\beta \right) }{\left( 1-Q\beta \right) }\alpha ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}\beta ^{\frac{-1}{1-\beta }}Q^{\frac{-\beta }{1-\beta }}=\frac{\alpha \left( 1-\beta \right) }{\left( 1-Q\beta \right) }\alpha ^{\frac{\beta }{1-\beta }}\beta ^{\frac{-\beta }{ 1-\beta }}\beta ^{-1}Q^{\frac{-\beta }{1-\beta }} \\ n&= \widetilde{n}=\left[ \frac{\alpha \left( 1-\beta \right) }{\beta \left( 1-Q\beta \right) }\right] ^{\frac{1}{1-\beta }}\left( \frac{\alpha }{Q\beta } \right) ^{\beta }. \end{aligned}$$

Note that

$$\begin{aligned} {u^{\prime} }\left( n_{2}\right)&= \frac{1}{n_{2}^{2}\left( 1-\beta \right) } \left( -\alpha +\alpha \beta -\alpha \frac{\beta }{\left( Q\frac{n_{2}}{ \alpha }\beta \right) ^{\frac{1}{\beta -1}}}+n_{2}\frac{\beta }{\left( Q \frac{n_{2}}{\alpha }\beta \right) ^{\frac{\beta }{\beta -1}}}\right) \\&= \frac{1}{n_{2}^{2}\left( 1-\beta \right) }\alpha \left( \beta \left( 1-Q\beta \right) \left( \frac{\delta }{Q\beta \delta -\delta +1}\right) -\left( 1-\beta \right) \right) , \end{aligned}$$

which is positive iff \(\delta >{\widetilde{\delta} }=\frac{1-\beta }{1-Q\beta }.\)

Thus, since \(\lim _{n\rightarrow 0}u(n)=\infty\) we obtain that \({\widetilde{n}} \equiv {\mathrm{argmin} }_{n\le n_{2}}u(n)<n_{2}\) iff \(\delta >{\widetilde{\delta} }=\frac{1-\beta }{1-Q\beta }.\) \(\square\)

From the previous lemma, \(u{( n) ^{\prime }}>0\) if and only if \(n\in \left( {\widetilde{ n}},n_{2}\right),\) which is possible only when \(\delta >{\widetilde{\delta}}.\) In the rest of cases, \(u\left( n\right) ^{\prime }<0.\) Since \(\lim _{n\rightarrow 0}u(n)=\infty,\) by the continuity of u, there exists an \({\widehat{n}}<\tilde{n}\) such that \(u({\widehat{n}})=u(n_{2}).\) Thus, legislators would never add new members if \(\delta \le {\widetilde{\delta}}\) or if \(n_{o}\notin \left( {\widehat{n}},n_{2}\right)\) when \(\delta > {\widetilde{\delta}}.\) In contrast, the size of the legislature increases up to \(n_{f}=n_{2}\) when \(n_{o}\in \left( {\widehat{n}},n_{2}\right)\) and \(\delta > {\widetilde{\delta} }\) (whenever this is possible; that is, assuming \(N\ge n_{2}\)). In the latter case, the collective good provision of the resulting legislature increases. This mitigates the original inefficiency because there is a Pareto improvement. However, neither \(y^{0}\left( n_{o}\right)\) nor \(y^{0}\left( n_{f}\right)\) is (generically) attained in equilibrium. This contrasts with the limiting case (\(\delta \rightarrow 1\)) where \(y^{0}\left( n_{f}\right) =1\) could be achieved. Nonetheless, as discussed, in that case \(y^{0}\left( n_{f}\right)\) does not coincide with \(y^{0}\left( n_{o}\right) <1.\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cardona, D., Rubí-Barceló, A. On the efficiency of equilibria in a legislative bargaining model with particularistic and collective goods. Public Choice 161, 345–366 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-014-0204-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-014-0204-0

Keywords

JEL Codes

Navigation