Skip to main content
Log in

The epistemology of ‘just is’-statements

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Agustín Rayo’s The Construction of Logical Space offers an exciting and ambitious defense of a broadly Carnapian approach to metaphysics. This essay will focus on one of the main differences between Rayo’s and Carnap’s approaches. Carnap distinguished between analytic, a priori “meaning postulates”, and empirical claims, which were both synthetic and knowable only a posteriori. Like meaning postulates, they determine the boundaries of logical space. But Rayo is skeptical that the a priori/a posteriori or analytic/synthetic distinctions can do the work Carnap wanted them to, so unlike meaning postulates, ‘just is’-statements aren’t assumed to be analytic or knowable a priori. This essay will concern the epistemology of ‘just is’-statements in Rayo’s picture. If not by a priori reflection, how can we determine which ones to accept? I’ll distinguish two competing strands in Rayo’s work. The less radical, Lewisian strand holds that the question of whether to accept a ‘just is’-statement can be addressed in a neutral, non-question-begging way, by a kind of cost-benefit analysis. The more radical, Kuhnian strand holds that there can be no ‘just is’-statement-independent, rational choice of which ‘just is’-statements to accept. I argue that Rayo faces strong internal pressure to adopt the Kuhnian picture. While it is possible for Rayo to resist these Kuhnian pressures, natural strategies for doing so leave his view more similar to Carnap’s than the above gloss suggested.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Carnap (1967, p. 176).

  2. See Kuhn (1962).

  3. See, e.g., Harman (1965), Lipton (2004).

  4. Rayo (2013, pp. 20–21). Moreover, this isn’t just an optional feature of his view; without this connection, it’s hard to see how ‘just is’-statements could have the connections to ‘why-closure’ that Rayo depends on them to have. (Rayo 2013, p. 54).

  5. Or at least, that this problem arises. Of course, there may well be other problems for such arguments that have nothing to do with the issues discussed in this essay.

  6. Of course, this inability to represent a posteriori learning of previously unintelligible hypotheses might be taken as a limitation of conceiving of learning along inference to the best explanation or Bayesian lines. See, e.g., Chihara (1987), who takes it to be a problem for Bayesianism that it cannot represent the rational credence changes that are driven by imagining new hypotheses. Still, in the absence of some alternative picture that can make sense of purely a posteriori learning of previously unintelligible hypotheses, it seems me that Rayo would be on shaky ground to insist that this is how learning ‘just is’-statements works.

  7. While the focus is quite different, there are some nice examples of learning events that don’t seem happily classified as either straightforwardly a priori or a posteriori in Williamson (2013).

  8. See, e.g., Kuhn (1962, p. 150).

  9. I have in mind especially the preface to Lewis (1986).

  10. See, e.g., van Fraassen (1980), Garfinkel (1981).

  11. See Rayo (2013, §2.2.4).

  12. See, e.g., Kuhn (1962, pp. 109–110).

  13. Plausibly, accepting a new ‘just is’-statement will typically involve losing the ability to explain, as well as being relieved of the burden to answer, infinitely many questions (at least in principle).

References

  • Block, N., & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review, 108, 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1967). The logical structure of the world [and] pseudoproblems in philosophy. London: Routledge K. Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chihara, C. (1987). Some problems for bayesian confirmation theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38(4), 551–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation: rethinking the questions in social theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. H. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. The Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge/Taylor and Francis Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. (2013). The construction of logical space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2013). How deep is the distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge? In A. Casullo & J. C. Thurow (Eds.), The a priori in philosophy (pp. 291–309). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Agustín Rayo, Jason Turner, and an audience at the 2014 Pacific APA.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Greco.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Greco, D. The epistemology of ‘just is’-statements. Philos Stud 172, 2599–2607 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0424-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0424-7

Keywords

Navigation