Skip to main content
Log in

How (not) to bring psychology and biology together

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Evolutionary psychologists often try to “bring together” biology and psychology by making predictions about what specific psychological mechanisms exist from theories about what patterns of behaviour would have been adaptive in the EEA for humans. This paper shows that one of the deepest methodological generalities in evolutionary biology—that proximate explanations and ultimate explanations stand in a many-to-many relation—entails that this inferential strategy is unsound. Ultimate explanations almost never entail the truth of any particular proximate hypothesis. But of course it does not follow that there are no other ways of “bringing together” biology and psychology. Accordingly, this paper explores one other strategy for doing just that, the pursuit of a very specific kind of consilience. However, I argue that inferences reflecting the pursuit of this kind of consilience with the best available theories in contemporary evolutionary biology indicate that psychologists should have a preference for explanations of adaptive behavior in humans that refer to learning and other similarly malleable psychological mechanisms—and not modules or instincts or any other kind of relatively innate and relatively non-malleable psychological mechanism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Accordingly, one way of reading Darwin’s Origin is to see the point of chapter 1, “Variation under domestication”, being that artificial selection is a sufficient ultimate explanation of some kinds of speciation, and then that the argument in subsequent chapters is that natural selection provides an analogous ultimate explanation of species that are, to put it simply, not domesticated.

  2. There is also an important caveat to the claim that, generally, true ultimate explanations do not entail the truth of any particular proximate explanations. For, if some particular pattern of adaptive behaviour did occur in the history of some organism, then it does follow, in a trivial sense, that the organism either has, or at least had, some psychological (or some other kind of proximate) mechanism that has (or had) the function of being able to cause the relevant pattern of behaviour. But it does not follow from this that there is a psychological (or proximate) mechanism the only function of which is to produce the relevant behaviour, since many different psychological mechanisms can satisfy such a functional description. For, again, it is a truism that, if an organism is able to produce a pattern of behaviour B, then some part of it has the function of being able to produce B. Call whatever has this function trait T. Now, note the language used to talk about T does not indicate whether or not T has any other functions. So T could of course be a psychological module, in which case its only significant function may be to produce behaviour B and it is also true that the possession of T is relatively innate and non-malleable. But T could also be information that was acquired from one-off peer learning, in which case its only function may be to produce B, and yet in this case the possession of T is extremely context dependent. What’s more, T could also be a domain-general psychological faculty, or even a system of faculties. In this case the total functional description of T would include the ability to cause B along with a host of other causal functions; indeed, this list might be infinitely long for a sufficiently complex system. These three different (types of) psychological mechanisms—a module, contextually-acquired information, and domain-general faculties or systems—can all be said to have the function being able to produce B. For this reason, it would be a mistake to infer that any specific proximate conclusions follow from the trivial fact that, if behaviour B was produced by an organism, some part of the organism has the functional ability to cause B.

  3. That is, at least until the emergence of evolutionary developmental biology. Importantly, the field’s leading journal, Evolution and Development, was founded in 1999.

References

  • Alcock, J. (2001). The triumph of sociobiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersson, M. (1994). Sexual selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1985). Observations, explanatory power, and simplicity. In P. Achinstein & O. Hannaway (Eds.), Observation, experiment, and hypothesis in modern physical science (pp. 349–378). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1990). Realism, approximate truth and philosophical method. In W. Savage (Ed.), Scientific theories, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 14, pp. 355–391). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (2001). Reference, (in)commensurability, and meaning: some (perhaps) unanticipated complexities. In P. Hoyningen-Huene & H. Sankey (Eds.), Incommensurability and related matters (pp. 1–63). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bradbury, J. W. (1981). The evolution of leks. In R. D. Alexander & D. W. Tinkle (Eds.), Natural selection and social behavior (pp. 138–169). New York: Chiron Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, R. (2008). Evolution and human behavior: Darwinian perspectives on human nature (2nd ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cimino, A., & Delton, A. W. (2010). On the perception of newcomers: Toward an evolved psychology of intergenerational coalitions. Human Nature, 21(2), 186–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2011). Prediction and explanation in historical natural science. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 551–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1990). The past explains the present: Emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology, 11, 375–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (1985). Child abuse and other risks of not living with both parents. Ethology and Sociobiology, 6(4), 197–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1984). The natural ontological attitude. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 83–107). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1983). Testing theoretical hypotheses. In J. Earman (Ed.), Testing scientific theories, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 10, pp. 269–298). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1990). Evolutionary models of science. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Evolution, cognition, and realism (pp. 21–32). Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Reconstructing constructivism: causal models, Bayesian learning mechanisms, and the theory theory. Psychological Bulletin, 138(6), 1085–1108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2008). Ethology, sociobiology, evolutionary psychology. In S. Sarkar & A. Plutyinski (Eds.), Blackwell’s companion to philosophy of biology (pp. 393–414). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, N., & Henrich, J. (2007). Why humans cooperate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2006). Evolution in four dimensions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvi, T., Sillén-Tullberg, B., & Wiklund, C. (1981). Individual versus kin selection for aposematic coloration: a reply to Harvey and Paxton. Oikos, 37(3), 393–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurzban, R. (2011). Why everyone (else) is a hypocrite: evolution and the modular mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2011). Discovery and confirmation in evolutionary psychology. In J. Prinz (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science, 134(3489), 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mineka, S., & Cook, M. (1988). Social learning and the acquisition of snake fear in monkeys. In T. R. Zentall & B. G. Galef Jr (Eds.), Social learning: psychological and biological perspectives (pp. 51–73). Hilladale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moczek, A. P., Sultan, S., Foster, S., Ledon-Rettig, C., Dworkin, I., Nijhout, H. F., et al. (2011). The role of developmental plasticity in evolutionary innovation. Proceedings of the Royal Society Biological Sciences, 278, 2705–2713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mora, C., Tittensor, D. P., Adl, S., Simpson, A. G. B., & Worm, B. (2011). How many species are there on earth and in the ocean? PLoS Biology, 9(8), e1001127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pfennig, D. W., & Sherman, P. W. (1995). Kin recognition. Scientific American, 272(6), 98–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1995). Is structural realism the best of both worlds? Dialectica, 49, 15–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2006). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlicting, C. D., & Smith, H. (2002). Phenotypic plasticity: linking molecular mechanisms with evolutionary outcomes. Evolutionary Ecology, 16, 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Syal, S., & Finlay, B. L. (2011). Thinking outside the cortex: Social motivation in the evolution and development of language. Developmental Science, 14(2), 417–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2000). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2009). Why we cooperate. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, H. T. P., & Lenton, T. M. (2007). Artificial selection of simulated microbial ecosystems. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104, 8918–8923.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimberger, P. H. (1991). Plasticity of jaw and skull morphology in the neotropical cichlids Geophagus brasiliensis and G. steindachneri. Evolution, 45, 1545–1563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu, F., & Kushnir, T. (Eds.) (2012). Rational constructivism in cognitive development. Academic Press—Elsevier, Waltham.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to the following for their helpful comments, criticisms, questions, and in one particular case, for several very good ideas too: Amy Allcock, Richard Boyd, Barbara Koslowski, Jane Dryden, Kate Cober, Robbie Moser, Roopen Majithia, Tamar Kushnir, and several anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Fedyk.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fedyk, M. How (not) to bring psychology and biology together. Philos Stud 172, 949–967 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0297-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0297-9

Keywords

Navigation