Skip to main content
Log in

Disagreement behind the veil of ignorance

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we argue that there is a kind of moral disagreement that survives the Rawlsian veil of ignorance. While a veil of ignorance eliminates sources of disagreement stemming from self-interest, it does not do anything to eliminate deeper sources of disagreement. These disagreements not only persist, but transform their structure once behind the veil of ignorance. We consider formal frameworks for exploring these differences in structure between interested and disinterested disagreement, and argue that consensus models offer us a solution concept for disagreements behind the veil of ignorance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, Rawls saw a version of this problem, which he called the ‘burdens of judgment.’ This motivated him to switch to the idea of the overlapping consensus in Political Liberalism (Rawls 2005).

  2. Note that these personal preferences need not be selfish: an altruist may fiercely pursue the well-being of those who are more disadvantaged than her. In such situations, an agreement on moral questions is transformed into a settlement of competing, position-dependent interests.

  3. The definition below is easily generalizable to more than three players.

  4. Consensus models were originally developed with factual disagreements in mind, but recent work on the topic has suggested that these models have wider applications (Steele et al. 2007; Martini et al. 2012).

  5. Formally, this amounts to matrix multiplication of the opinion vector by the weights matrix.

  6. Besides, an agent who refused to be rational and listen to her peers in the Original Position would surely violate the spirit of Rawls’ thought experiment in a fundamental way.

  7. These weights need not depend on how close the agents are to each other with regard to their respective estimates. Using distance between estimates as a measure of respect was advocated by Regan et al. (2006) for pragmatic reasons and also by Hegselmann and Krause (2002). The model permits us to assign relative weights as a function of the difference of opinion, if this is desired, but it is not required.

References

  • Babcock, L., Loewenstein, G., Issacharoff, S., & Camerer, C. (1995). Biased judgments of fairness in bargaining. The American Economic Review, 85(5), 1337–1343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Babcock, L., & Loewenstein, G. (1997). Explaining bargaining impasse: The role of self-serving biases. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 11(1), 109–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C., & Mercier, H. (2013). Self-serving biases and public justifications in trust games. Synthese, 190(5), 909–922.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1994). Game theory and the social contract, Vol. 1: Playing fair. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1998). Game theory and the social contract, Vol. 2: Just playing. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, J. H. (1973). Group decision and social interaction: A theory of social decision schemes. Psychological Review, 80, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGroot, M. (1974). Reaching a consensus. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 69, 118–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, J. R. P. Jr. (1956). A formal theory of social power. Psychological Review, 63(3), 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1986). Morals by agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, R., & Krause, U. (2002). Opinion Dynamics and bounded confidence models, analysis, and simulation. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 5(3). http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/5/3/2.html.

  • Lehrer, K. (1976). When rational disagreement is impossible. Noûs, 10(3), 327–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Wagner, C. (1981). Rational consensus in science and society. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martini, C., Sprenger, J., & Colyvan, M. (2012). Resolving disagreement through mutual respect. Erkenntnis.

  • Nash, J. (1950). Equilibrium points in N-person games. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 36(1), 48–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pronin, E., Lin, D., & Ross, L. (2002). The bias blind spot: Perceptions of bias in self versus others. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28(3), 369–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2005). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, H. M., Colyvan M., & Markovchick-Nicholls, L. (2006). A formal model for consensus and negotiation in environmental management. Journal of Environmental Management, 80(2), 167–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steele, K., Regan, H. M., Colyvan, M., & Burgman, M. A. (2007). Right decisions or happy decision makers?. Social Epistemology, 21(4), 349–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, C. (1978). Consensus through respect: A model of rational group decision-making. Philosophical Studies, 34, 335–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank Samuel Freeman, Douglas Paletta, Gerald Gaus, and the audience of the Conference ‘New Directions in the Philosophy of Science’ held at the Bertinoro Conference Centre (University of Bologna) for their useful comments on earlier versions of the manuscript. The usual exculpations apply. Part of this work was funded by a Dutch Science Foundation Internationalisation Grant.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryan Muldoon.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Summary of the Lehrer–Wagner model

Let \(G = \{1, \ldots N\}\) be a group of agents. The Lehrer–Wagner model is concerned with the problem of estimating an unknown quantity x from the individual estimates x i of every group member i. This quantity x is thought of as objective and independent of the group members’ cognitive states.

Lehrer and Wagner’s central idea consists in ascribing the agents beliefs about each other’s expertise, or in other words, mutual degrees of respect for the issue at hand. These weights w ij represent the respect that agent i has for agent j, relative to the subject matter in question, and describe the proportion to which j’s opinion affects i’s revised opinion. The mutual respect assignments are in an N × N matrix W:

$$ W = \left( \begin{array}{llll} w_{11} & w_{12} & \dots & w_{1N} \\ w_{21} & w_{22} & \dots & w_{2N} \\ \dots & \dots & \dots & \dots \\ w_{N1} & w_{N2} & \dots & w_{NN} \end{array}\right). $$

An important mathematical constraint is that the values in each row are nonnegative and normalized so as to sum to 1: ∑ N j=1 w ij  = 1. Then, W is multiplied with a vector \(\vec{x} = (x_{1}, \ldots, x_{N})\) that contains the agents’ individual estimates of x, obtaining a novel updated value for \(\vec{x}\):

$$ W \cdot \vec{x} = \left( \begin{array}{l} w_{11} x_{1} + w_{12} x_2+ \ldots + w_{1N} x_N\\ w_{21} x_{1} + w_{22} x_2 + \ldots + w_{2N} x_N \\ \dots \\ w_{N1} x_{1} + w_{N2} x_2 + \ldots + w_{NN} x_N \end{array}\right). $$

In general, however, this procedure will not directly lead to consensus, since the entries of \(W \cdot \vec{x}\) differ: \((W\vec{x})_{i} \neq (W\vec{x})_{j}\). However, it can be shown that the iterated application of the pooling procedure represented by WW n, converges to the so-called “consensus matrix” \(W^{\infty}\). It can also be shown that the individual entries of \(W^{\infty} \cdot \vec{x}\) are equal to each other. Thus, repeating the pooling procedure leads to (rational) consensus.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Colyvan, M. et al. Disagreement behind the veil of ignorance. Philos Stud 170, 377–394 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0225-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0225-4

Keywords

Navigation