Skip to main content
Log in

The accomplishment of plans: a new version of the principle of double effect

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The classical principle of double effect offers permissibility conditions for actions foreseen to lead to evil outcomes. I shall argue that certain kinds of closeness cases, as well as general heuristic considerations about the order of explanation, lead us to replace the intensional concept of intention with the extensional concept of accomplishment in double effect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. According to some moral views, the death of an innocent will not count as an evil in this sense when it saves the same individual from grave suffering and according to some other views it will not count as an evil when it is commanded by God.

  2. Cf. Mangan (1949).

  3. Bennett (2001).

  4. Knobe (2003).

  5. Davidson (1963).

  6. E.g., Wilson (1989) and Ginet (1990).

  7. But might we not cite a specific Richter rating of the earthquake in a more precise explanation? We can easily imagine saying that the building survived because it was designed for earthquakes rated up to 8.5 on the Richter scale, while the earthquake in question was an 8.3. This is a more difficult case. I am inclined to say the following. That the earthquake was an 8.3 is equivalent to the conjunction of two claims, namely that the earthquake was at most 8.3 and that it was at least 8.3, and only the fact that the earthquake was at most 8.3 belongs in the explanation [here I am mindful of Wesley Salmon’s maxim that “irrelevancies (are) harmless to arguments but fatal to explanations” (Salmon 1990), though I draw a different lesson than he does], the fact that it was at least 8.3 not making a positive contribution to the explanation, though it might provide pragmatically relevant background information. But I do not need to defend this here in order to defend the particular claim that foreseen deaths of the civilians do not enter into the explanation of the strategic bomber’s action. It is also worth noting that one might instead allow that the agent’s foreseeing the deaths enters into the explanation, but does so negatively by being a factor opposed to the explanandum, and not as expressing the agent’ aim.

  8. An anonymous reader has suggested that perhaps being human explains being a mammal and hence this example does not work. But it does not follow from the explanatory claim that an intention to kill this mammal implies an intention to kill a human. Intention cuts more finely than such explanatory connections. Even if the victim’s being a human in fact explains the victim’s being a mammal, Sam might not agree with this metaphysical claim, and Sam’s intentions depend on what Sam thinks is the case. And even if Sam were to learn that this explanatory claim is correct, his learning it might not be motivationally relevant to him, and hence the explanatory claim would not affect his intentions.

  9. Bennett (2001) considers but does not adopt an extensionalizing of intention as one solution to some of the problems of double effect.

  10. For discussions of action plans, see Bratman (1987) and, more recently, Murphy (2004).

  11. For a defense, see Murphy (1997).

  12. The term is of course from Williams (1976).

  13. Bennett (2001).

  14. Even people like Descartes who think it is possible to have a causa sui should not dispute this principle in the cases in which I need it.

  15. The term is from Cavanaugh (2006).

  16. Some might think that it is likely permissible to impose an evil on someone with that person’s consent. Such ethicists will need to modify PDE2 to be a sufficient but not necessary condition for permissibility.

  17. Delaney (2008).

  18. “The idea that one can determine one’s intentions by making such a little speech to oneself is obvious bosh” (Anscombe 2000).

  19. FitzPatrick (2006).

  20. Kamm (2000).

  21. Olson (1997).

  22. There may also be fine-grained evils, such as the fine-grained event of this innocent human dying. But the fine-grained event of the zookeeper dying perhaps won’t be an evil, since it is not an evil that a zookeeper dies but only that an innocent human zookeeper dies.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (2000). Intention (p. 42). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (2001). Foreseen side effects versus intended consequences. In P. A. Woodward (Ed.), The doctrine of double effect (pp. 85–118). Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1987). Intentions, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavanaugh, T. A. (2006). Double-effect reasoning: Doing good and avoiding evil. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons and causes. Journal of Philosophy, 60, 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delaney, N. F. (2008). Two cheers for ‘closeness’: Terror, targeting and double effect. Philosophical Studies, 137, 335–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • FitzPatrick, W. J. (2006). The intend/foresee distinction and the problem of ‘closeness’. Philosophical Studies, 128, 585–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1990). On action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. M. (2000). The doctrine of triple effect and why a rational agent need not intend the means to his end. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 74, 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63, 190–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mangan, J. (1949). An historical analysis of the principle of double effect. Theological Studies, 10, 41–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. C. (1997). The conscience principle. Journal of Philosophical Research, 22, 387–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. C. (2004). Intention, foresight, and success. In S. Oderberg & T. Chappell (Eds.), Human values: New essays on ethics and natural law (pp. 252–268). London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, Eric. (1997). The human animal: Personal identity without psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poore, G. S. (2010). A double take on double effect: What is the principle of double effect supposed to establish? Presented at the Baylor symposium on faith and culture: Human dignity and the future of health care.

  • Salmon, W. (1990). Four decades of scientific explanation (p. 102). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1976). Moral luck. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume L, 115–135.

  • Wilson, G. (1989). The intentionality of human action. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Neil Delaney, Daniel Hill, Anthony McCarthy, Jonathan Kvanvig, Christopher Tollefsen, Ryan Wasserman, Helen Watt, audiences at Georgetown and Baylor Universities, and anonymous referees for discussions and comments. I especially would like to thank Mark Murphy, as this paper grew out of years of discussions of double effect issues with him.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander R. Pruss.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pruss, A.R. The accomplishment of plans: a new version of the principle of double effect. Philos Stud 165, 49–69 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9925-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9925-4

Keywords

Navigation