Skip to main content
Log in

Moral normativity

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is a platitude that morality is normative, but a substantive and interesting question whether morality is normative in a robust and important way; and although it is often assumed that morality is indeed robustly normative, that view is by no means uncontroversial, and a compelling argument for it is conspicuously lacking. In this paper, I provide such an argument. I argue, based on plausible claims about the relationship between moral wrongs and moral criticizability, and the relationship between criticizability and normative reasons, that moral facts necessarily confer normative reasons upon moral agents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the purposes of this paper, I assume the truth of moral cognitivism. That is, I assume that moral predicates denote properties, thus that typical sentences in which they occur express propositions, and that moral judgments are beliefs.

  2. Parfit (2011).

  3. See, e.g., Mackie (1977), Joyce (2001, 2006).

  4. See, e.g., Scanlon (1998), Parfit (2011).

  5. E.g., Foot (1972), Williams (1981), Railton (1986), Boyd (1988).

  6. Joyce (2001), p. 208.

  7. Although PMN is not Joyce’s precise formulation, his is equivalent to PMN.

  8. See, e.g., Schroeder (2008, 2009), Way (2009), Vogelstein (2012).

  9. See Vogelstein (2011) for the argument that there is no compelling reason to believe that moral reasons are reasons for action. It is argued there that moral reasons are in fact reasons for having sentiments of a certain sort.

  10. See, e.g., Strawson (1960) and Wallace (1994). More specifically, on this view to morally blame another person A for ϕ-ing is to feel resentment or indignation towards A for ϕ-ing. To morally blame oneself for ϕ-ing is to feel guilty for ϕ-ing. Furthermore, the same attitude/expression distinction discussed above with respect to criticism applies to moral blame—the attitude of moral blame is to be distinguished from the expression of blame, or the act of blaming.

  11. Perhaps the non-reactive moralist even feels a deep sympathy, compassion, or pity towards moral wrongdoers, for being so lost in their ways.

  12. Pereboom (2001), p. 150.

  13. Slote (1990), pp. 377–8.

  14. Ibid., p. 377.

  15. Ibid., p. 378.

  16. The idea here is that there are degrees of blamelessness (and this is plausible—it seems that one can be more or less morally responsible for one’s actions), and that a case of maximum blamelessness is the best prospect for a case in which one is not criticizable for one’s morally wrong action.

  17. We need not commit to the claim that the criticizer always has an explicit or consciously recognized belief about the criticized person’s best reasons; the claim is simply that criticism involves feeling disrespect (or some suitably similar attitude) for the reason that someone has failed to comply with her best reasons, which may not involve explicit belief.

References

  • Boyd, D. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 181–228). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philosophical Review, 81, 305–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2001). The myth of morality. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2006). The evolution of morality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. New York: Pelican.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1986). Moral realism. Philosophical Review, 95, 163–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2008). Having reasons. Philosophical Studies, 139, 57–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2009). Means-end coherence, stringency, and subjective reasons. Philosophical Studies, 143, 223–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (1990). Ethics without free will. Social Theory and Practice, 16, 369–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1974). Freedom and resentment. In P. F. Strawson (Ed.), Freedom and resentment and other essays. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogelstein, E. (2011). Morality, reasons, and sentiments. Philosophical Studies, 155, 421–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogelstein, E. (2012). Subjective rReasons. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 15, 239–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Way, J. (2009, December). Two accounts of the Normativity of Rationality. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy: http://jesp.org/articles/download/TwoAccountsOfTheNormativityOfRationality.pdf. Accessed 13 Aug 2012.

  • Williams, B. (1981). Internal and external reasons. In Moral luck (pp. 101–103) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Vogelstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Vogelstein, E. Moral normativity. Philos Stud 165, 1083–1095 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0010-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0010-9

Keywords

Navigation