Skip to main content
Log in

How to be a minimalist about sets

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to the iterative conception of set, sets can be arranged in a cumulative hierarchy divided into levels. But why should we think this to be the case? The standard answer in the philosophical literature is that sets are somehow constituted by their members. In the first part of the paper, I present a number of problems for this answer, paying special attention to the view that sets are metaphysically dependent upon their members. In the second part of the paper, I outline a different approach, which circumvents these problems by dispensing with the priority or dependence relation altogether. Along the way, I show how this approach enables the mathematical structuralist to defuse an objection recently raised against her view.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the remainder of this paper, I will dispense with the use of quotation marks to signal the distinction between use and mention, whenever this aids readability without jeopardizing understanding.

  2. The diagnosis of the paradoxes offered here is indebted to that offered in Rieger (2009).

  3. In technical terms, we say that a set is pure iff no individuals belong to its transitive closure.

  4. The issue of which of the ZFC axioms are sanctioned by the iterative conception was famously discussed by Boolos (1971, 1989), who argued that Choice, Extensionality and Replacement do not follow from the conception. Now the axioms of Z do include Extensionality. However, Boolos’s point with regards to this axiom seems to be that our reasons for accepting it are that it serves to distinguish sets from other entities, rather than that it is sanctioned by a certain conception of set. This seems right, but it seems to apply to other conceptions of set as well, as Paseau (2007, 44–46) has, to my mind, convincingly argued. Having said that, it would perhaps be more correct to say that the axioms of Z are sanctioned by the iterative conception and the concept of set. For ease of exposition, however, I will drop the qualification in the remainder of this paper.

  5. More precisely, Separation is the schema: \(\forall z \exists y \forall x (x \in y \leftrightarrow x \in z \wedge \phi(x)),\) where ϕ(x) is, again, any formula in \(\fancyscript{L}_{\in}\) in which x is free and which contains no free occurrences of y.

  6. Set-theorists put the matter by saying that the formula \(y = \fancyscript{P}(x)\) is not absolute for transitive models, where a model \({\mathfrak{A}}\) is said to be transitive iff every element of \({\mathfrak{A}}\) which is not an individual is also a subset of \({\mathfrak{A}}.\) In set theory a formula ϕ with free variables \(x_1, \ldots, x_n\) is said to be absolute for a model \({\mathfrak{A}}\) iff \({(\forall x_1, \ldots, x_n \in \mathfrak{A}) (\phi(x_{1}, \ldots, x_{n}) \leftrightarrow \phi^{\mathfrak{A}}(x_{1}, \ldots, x_{n}))},\) where \(\phi^{\mathfrak{A}}\) is the relativization of ϕ to \({\mathfrak{A}}\) obtained in the usual manner (i.e. by replacing ∀x and ∃x by, respectively, \({\forall x \in \mathfrak{A}}\) and \({\exists x \in \mathfrak{A}}\)). Effectively, this means that if ϕ is absolute for transitive models, to ascertain whether the property expressed by ϕ holds of a set, it is enough to ascertain whether ϕ holds of that set in any transitive model (and similarly for the case of relations). This cannot be done in the case of \(y = \fancyscript{P}(x),\) since y may be the set of all subsets of x in a certain transitive model and yet not be its powerset in the cumulative hierarchy: we can never rule out that, when we consider the whole set-theoretic universe, subsets can become definable that were not definable before, thereby affecting the truth-value of \(y = \fancyscript{P}(x).\) See Hallett (1984, 206–207) and Jech (2003, 163, 185) for more on the notion of absoluteness.

  7. ‘We may also appeal to the reflection principles to argue that the unbounded quantifiers are not really unbounded’ (Wang 1974, 209).

  8. That is: \(\forall v \exists!w \phi (v, w) \rightarrow \forall u \exists y \forall x (x \in y \leftrightarrow \exists v (v \in u \wedge \phi(v, x))\). What this says, effectively, is that the image of a set in a first-order specifiable function is a set.

  9. That is, by defining ‘it is possible that p’ as ‘it is not necessary that not p.’

  10. In fact, there are theories which, albeit consistent if ZF is, allow for sets of this kind. The most famous examples, perhaps, are the four theories described by Aczel (1988), all of which are obtained by replacing ZFC ’s Axiom of Foundation with an anti-foundation axiom.

  11. Of course, as Lowe himself is eager to stress, endorsing the claim that everything depends upon itself does not commit one to the claim that everything depends solely upon itself.

  12. To be sure, in the quoted passage Cameron is not dealing with the question whether the membership relation has certain structural properties. The point is just that, if someone wants to use the notion of metaphysical dependence to motivate certain structural features of the membership relation, they cannot rely on our understanding of the membership relation to motivate the structural features of the relation of metaphysical dependence.

  13. Strictly speaking, what we are describing here is non-eliminative structuralism. Eliminative structuralism combines the insight that mathematical theories describe structures with an attempt to avoid commitment to an ontology of structures. See Linnebo (2008, 60–61) for more on the distinction, and for a careful description of different brands of non-eliminative structuralism.

  14. See Linnebo (2008, 66–68) for evidence that Resnik too is committed to the dependence claim, albeit less explicitly.

  15. The approach might be anticipated by some brief remarks in Boolos (1989, 90–91; 2000, 126–127), and is, to my knowledge, never considered in recent discussions of the iterative conception.

  16. Elsewhere, Gödel (1947, 180, fn, 13) also points out that albeit the expression ‘set of x’s’ cannot be defined away, it can be paraphrased by other expressions such as ‘combination of any number of x’s’, of which, he says, it is reasonable to claim that we have an independent grasp.

  17. To be precise, this is Horwich’s view as expressed in the first edition of Horwich (1998). In response to criticisms, Horwich has slightly modified his view about what the minimal theory of truth should comprise. However, the point is irrelevant for our present concerns, since his reasons for taking something to be part of the minimal theory remain the same. For details, the reader can consult the postscript to the second edition of Horwich’s book.

  18. Some arguments to this effect are offered in Fine (1994). For the record, I do not find these arguments very convincing, but, for reasons of space, I cannot discuss them here.

References

  • Aczel, P. (1988). Non-well-founded sets. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1971). The iterative conception of set. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 215–231. Reprinted in Logic, logic, and logic, pp. 13–29, by Boolos, 1998, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Boolos, G. (1989). Iteration again. Philosophical Topics, 17, 5–21. Reprinted in Logic, logic, and logic, pp. 88–104, by Boolos, 1998, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Boolos, G. (2000). Must we believe in set theory? In G. Sher & R. Tieszen (Eds.), Between logic and intuition: Essays in honor of Charles Parsons (pp. 257–268). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Logic, logic, and logic, pp. 120–132, by Boolos, 1998, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Cameron, R. (2008). Turtles all the way down: Regress, priority and fundamentality. Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, K. (1993). The joy of sets. Fundamentals of contemporary set theory (2nd ed.). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 8: Logic and language (pp. 1–16). Atascadero: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). Ontological dependence. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95, 269–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1947). What is Cantor’s continuum problem? American Mathematical Monthly, 54, 515–525. Reprinted in Collected works II, pp. 176–187, by Gödel, 1990, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gödel, K. *(1951). Some basic theorems on the foundations of mathematics and their implications. In K. Gödel, Collected works III (pp. 304–323). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.

  • Hallett, M. (1984). Cantorian set theory and limitation of size. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1998). Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jech, T. (2003). Set theory. The third millennium edition. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2008). Structuralism and the notion of dependence. Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 59–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2003). Individuation. In M. Loux & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 75–95). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2005). Ontological dependence. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/dependence-ontological.

  • Lowe, E. J. (2007). Sortals and the individuation of objects. Mind and Language, 22, 514–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy. A naturalistic method. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, C. (2008). Mathematical thought and its objects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paseau, A. (2007). Boolos on the justification of set theory. Philosophia Mathematica, 15, 30–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, M. (2004). Set theory and its philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2006). Doubt truth to be a liar. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. (1997). Mathematics as a science of patterns. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieger, A. (2009). Paradox, ZF , and the axiom of foundation. In P. Clark, D. DeVidi, & M. Hallett (Eds.), Essays in honour of John L. Bell. Springer, Netherlands. http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/3810/.

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In: D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2000). Thinking about mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2006). Structure and identity. In F. MacBride (Ed.), Identity and modality (pp. 109–145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (2008). Identity, indiscernibility, and ante rem structuralism: The tale of i and −i. Philosophia Mathematica, 16, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, H. (1974). From mathematics to philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Tim Bays, Tim Button, Mic Detlefsen, Hannes Leitgeb, Hugh Mellor, Alex Oliver, Michael Potter, Peter Smith, Rob Trueman, Sean Walsh and Nathan Wildman. Earlier versions of this material were presented at a meeting of the Cambridge Serious Metaphysics Group and at the Foundations of Mathematics Seminar, University of Paris 7—Diderot. I am grateful to the members of these audiences for their valuable feedback. Research for this paper was made possible by a Research Fellowship from Magdalene College, Cambridge. I gratefully acknowledge the support of this institution.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luca Incurvati.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Incurvati, L. How to be a minimalist about sets. Philos Stud 159, 69–87 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9690-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9690-1

Keywords

Navigation