Skip to main content
Log in

Cognitive phenomenology and conscious thought

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

How does mental content feature in conscious thought? I first argue that for a thought to be conscious the content of that thought must conscious, and that one has to appeal to cognitive phenomenology to give an adequate account of what it is for the content of a thought to be conscious. Sensory phenomenology cannot do the job. If one claims that the content of a conscious thought is unconscious, one is really claiming that there is no such thing as conscious thought. So one must either accept that there is such a thing as cognitive phenomenology, or deny the existence of conscious thought. Once it is clear that conscious thought requires cognitive phenomenology, there is a pressing question about the exact relationship between a thought’s cognitive phenomenological properties and its content. I conclude with a discussion of the nature of this relationship.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This definition of ‘cognitive phenomenology’ differs from the one offered by Smithies 2013, who defines it as whatever phenomenology happens to be tied up with conscious thought. Defining it in this latter way seems to obscure the central question of the cognitive phenomenology debate, which is whether there is such a thing as cognitive phenomenology at all.

  2. There may be other kinds of phenomenology irreducible to either sensory phenomenology or cognitive phenomenology. For example, I argue (2009, 2014) that emotions have their own sui generis kind of phenomenology, and others have argued that there is sui generis agentive phenomenology. For the purposes of this paper, I will only be concerned to argue for sui generis cognitive phenomenology.

  3. Philosophers have explicated the distinction between internal and external representational content in various ways. See e.g. Chalmers 2002; Horgan and Tienson 2002; McGinn 1997. Rather than going into detail about these different theories, and how they compare to my explication, I am only interested in giving a very rough and intuitive characterization of what I have in mind.

  4. There are at least two ways of explicating the sense in which phenomenology is an intrinsic feature of conscious thought: one could hold a same-order self-intimating view, according to which a conscious thought is conscious in virtue of its self-intimating character, or simply hold that phenomenology is an intrinsic feature of conscious thought.

  5. I argue for this in detail in Montague (forthcoming a).

  6. See my Montague (forthcoming b) for a detailed argument against higher-order views. See also Neander 1998 and Zahavi 2006.

  7. Prinz 2011: 189-90.

  8. At this point, one might argue that there is a difference between the kinds of properties sensed and the kinds of properties thought about, and this difference between properties accounts for why the former are associated with phenomenology while the latter are not. (I thank an anonymous referee for raising this issue.) In order for this kind of objection to have force, and not just amount to the denial of cognitive phenomenology, more needs to be said about what this difference between kinds of properties is and how it is related to phenomenology.

  9. See Horgan and Tienson 2002; Kriegel 2013; Pitt 2004 and Strawson 2011 for discussion of this issue.

  10. The expression ‘taking herself to be thinking p’ in the phrase ‘a subject’s taking herself to be thinking p’ shouldn’t be understood as strictly involving propositional structure. There is a sense in which any deployment of a concept, even in the case of a dog if dogs deploy concepts, involves a ‘taking’. Moreover, this expression should not be understood as a subject’s having some higher-order thought towards her thinking that p. I just mean for this expression to indicate how things ‘phenomenologically seem’ to the subject from her first-person perspective.

  11. To see how a similar issue arises for the case of perception see Montague 2013.

  12. I find Dretske’s 1995 argument for phenomenal externalism based on the twin-earth water case unconvincing. His argument relies on rejecting the awareness of awareness thesis, which I accept, and argue for in Montague (forthcoming b).

  13. At this point I’m putting aside the possibility of sui generis emotional phenomenology and sui generis agentive phenomenology.

  14. The issue becomes more difficult if basic concepts can be complex. We then need to give some sense to the idea of how a concept can be basic and complex, and then ask how we grasp such complex concepts (do we grasp the whole without grasping the parts, or grasp the whole in virtue of grasping the parts?). These questions are for another time.

References

  • Block, N. (2002). Concepts of consciousness. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). The Components of Content. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2009). Multiple Drafts Model. In T. Bayne, A. Cleeremans, & P. Wilken (Eds.), The Oxford companion to consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Phenomenal externalism or if meanings ain’t in the head, Where are Qualia? Philosophical Issues, 7, 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2013). Phenomenal intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1997). The character of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, M. (2009). The Logic, Intentionality, and Phenomenology of Emotion. Philosophical Studies, 145(2), 171–192.

  • Montague, M. (2013). The Access Problem. In U. Kriegel (Ed.) Phenomenal intentioality: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Montague, M. (2014). Evaluative Phenomenology. In S. Roeser and C. Todd (Eds.) Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Montague, M. (forthcoming a). The Life of the Mind. In P. Coates and S. Coleman (Eds.) The nature of phenomenal qualities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Montague, M. (forthcoming b). The Given: Experience and its content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Neander, K. (1998). The division of phenomenal labor: a problem for representational theories of consciousness. Philosophical Perspectives, 12, 411–34.

  • Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2011). The sensory basis of cognitive phenomenology. In T. Bayne & M. Montague (Eds.), Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1819-1859/2010). The World as Will and Representation, vol. 1. (trans: Norman, J. et al.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Smithies, D. (2013). The nature of cognitive phenomenology. Philosophy Compass, 8(8), 744–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2011). Cognitive phenomenology: real life. In T. Bayne & M. Montague (Eds.), Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2006). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michelle Montague.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Montague, M. Cognitive phenomenology and conscious thought. Phenom Cogn Sci 15, 167–181 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9403-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9403-x

Keywords

Navigation