Skip to main content
Log in

Doing the best for one’s child: satisficing versus optimizing parentalism

  • Commentary
  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The maxim “parents should do what is in the best interests of their child” seems like an unassailable truth, and yet, as I argue here, there are serious problems with it when it is taken seriously. One problem concerns the sort of demands such a principle places on parents; the other concerns its larger social implications when conceived as part of a national policy for the rearing of children. The theory of parenting that creates these problems I call “optimizing parentalism.” To avoid them, I define and defend a new and more morally appealing theory, “satisficing parentalism.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, best interest should be understood holistically, as optimizing the satisfaction of some combination of interests, and not, as my example suggests, optimizing the satisfaction of interests, considered individually. This is an extremely important qualification, but I shall not pursue it here.

  2. See, for example, Philip Pettit’s response to Slote [2] and Ben Bradley [3].

  3. Consequentialism is not only a theory about rightness but also obligation. Rightness depends on the goodness of consequences, and we are obligated to do what is right, thus conceived.

  4. There is an additional problem with optimizing that I will not discuss here related to families with more than one child. If parents optimize for one child, they may not be able to optimize for the others.

  5. This is not to deny that there is a sense in which parenthood is autonomy-enhancing as well.

  6. See Norman Daniels’ distinction between restricted Ideal Advocates and unrestricted Ideal Advocates in [6, pp. 234-238].

References

  1. Salter, Erica K. 2012. Deciding for a child: a comprehensive analysis of the best interest standard. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. doi:10.1007/s11017-012-9219-z.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Slote, Michael, and Philip Pettit. 1984. Satisficing consequentialism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 58(suppl.):139–176.

  3. Bradley, Ben. 2006. Against satisficing consequentialism. Utilitas 18: 97–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. O’Neill, Onora. 1979. Begetting, bearing, and rearing. In Having children, ed. O. O’Neill, and W. Ruddick, 25–38. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Little, Margaret. 2003. The morality of abortion. In Ethical issues in modern medicine, 6th ed, ed. B. Steinbock, J. Arras, and A. London, 492–500. Boston: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Daniels, Norman. 2008. Just health. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Bronfenbrenner, Urie. 1972. Who cares for America’s children? In The future of the family, ed. L.K. Howe, 139–150. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Adrienne Asch, William Ruddick, and David Wasserman for their help, both in conversation and in written comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeffrey Blustein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Blustein, J. Doing the best for one’s child: satisficing versus optimizing parentalism. Theor Med Bioeth 33, 199–205 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-012-9222-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-012-9222-4

Keywords

Navigation