Skip to main content
Log in

Equidynamics and reliable reasoning about frequencies

Michael Strevens: Tychomancy: Inferring probability from causal structure. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 265pp, $39.95 HB

  • Book Symposium
  • Published:
Metascience Aims and scope

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. I will use “equidynamic” more generally to refer to arguments of the type that such reasoning would embody.

  2. Concepts of innateness are often problematic (Griffiths 2009), and Strevens’ sense of “innate” isn’t specified in detail, although he distinguishes the claim that equidynamic reasoning is innate from the claim that equidynamic reasoning is universal among humans (207). Drawing on a concept of environmentally relativized innateness from O’Neill (2014), I would characterize Strevens’ view as that equidynamic reasoning capabilities are innate in the sense that they almost always develop in those conditions in which humans almost always find themselves.

  3. Recent related mathematical work includes (Keller 1986; Diaconis 1998; Engel 1992).

  4. Note that although equidynamic reasoning processes would be heuristic, in that they start from simplifying assumptions and are not guaranteed to produce correct conclusions, Strevens’ proposal does not constitute a contribution to the bounded rationality research program, since his heuristics seem complex and difficult rather than “fast and frugal” (e.g., Gigerenzer and Selten 2001).

  5. In what follows, I will make no distinction between unconscious processes of inference, and other computational processes whose inputs could be described by premises of an inference, and whose outputs could be described by its conclusion, but which do not make use of propositional representations (see e.g., Haugeland 1997).

  6. Note that many evolutionary biologists hold that such adaptationist hypotheses—that such and such organisms have trait T because having T seems adaptive—typically need significant further justification (cf. Gould and Lewontin 1979).

  7. Among other things, I should not have had to work as hard as I have to convince other philosophers of biology that outcomes in biological environments exhibit sensitive dependence on particularities of environmental conditions, if this point were obvious to most people, as Strevens suggests (136).

  8. Strevens argues that Darwinian theory was from its origin based on underlying equidynamic reasoning, motivating this view with several instances in which Darwin uses words such as “chance.” Much of Darwin’s language has a deterministic flavor, however. Detailed historical scholarship would be needed to establish the claim that Darwin’s thinking about evolution was not merely intermittently or vaguely probabilistic, given that it was not particularly mathematical (Ariew 2007).

  9. The word “unsystematic” is intended to rule out, for example, cases in which an infant can see that an experimenter intentionally behaved as if seeking balls of a specific color. “Jumbled” is intended to be vague, as befits a rule based on flexible pattern matching.

  10. http://www.newappsblog.com/2013/11/michael-strevens-replies.html.

References

  • Abrams, M. 2012a. Mechanistic probability. Synthese 187(2): 343–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, M. 2012b. Mechanistic social probability: How individual choices and varying circumstances produce stable social patterns. In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Social Science (Chapter 9), ed. Harold Kincaid, 184–226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A. 2007. Under the influence of Malthus’s law of population growth: Darwin eschews the statistical techniques of Adolphe Quetelet. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38: 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denison, S., Reed, C., and F. Xu. 2013. The emergence of probabilistic reasoning in very young infants: Evidence from 4.5- and 6-month-olds. Developmental Psychology 49(2): 243–249.

  • Dewar, K., and F. Xu. 2010. Induction, overhypothesis, and the origin of abstract knowledge—Evidence from 9-month-old infants. Psychological Science 21(12): 1871–1877.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diaconis, P. 1998. A place for philosophy? The rise of modeling in statistical science. Quarterly of Applied Mathematics 56: 797–805.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, E. 1992. A road to randomness in physical systems. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fontanari, L., M. Gonzalez, G. Vallortigara, and V. Girotto. 2014. Probabilistic cognition in two indigenous Mayan groups. PNAS 111(48): 17075–17080.

  • Gigerenzer, G., and R. Selten. (eds.). 2001. Bounded rationality: The adaptive toolbox. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 1999. The scientist in the crib. New York: William Morrow and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., and R. C. Lewontin. 1979. The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences 205(1161): 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. 2009. The distinction between innate and acquired characteristics. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University, Fall 2009 ed. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/innate-acquired/.

  • Haugeland, J (ed.). 1997. Mind design II: Philosophy, psychology, and artificial intelligence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. 2013. Review of Tychomancy: Inferring probability from causal structure. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  • Keller, J. B. 1986. The probability of heads. The American Mathematical Monthly 93(3): 191–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myrvold, W. C. 2012. Deterministic laws and epistemic chances. In Probability in Physics, eds. Meir Hemmo and Yemima ben Menahem, pp. 73–85. Berlin: Springer.

  • O’Neill, E. 2014. Relativizing innateness: Innateness as the insensitivity of the appearance of a trait with respect to specified environmental variation. Biology & Philosophy 1–15. doi:10.1007/s10539-014-9465-8.

  • Poincaré, H. 1896. Calcul des Probabilités (1st ed.). Gauthier-Villars.

  • Rosenthal, J. 2010. The natural-range conception of probability. In Time, chance, and reduction: Philosophical aspects of statistical mechanics, ed. G. Ernst, and A. Hüttemann, 71–90. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, J. 2012. Probabilities as ratios of ranges in initial-state spaces. Journal of Logic, Language, and Inference 21: 217–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 1998. Inferring probabilities from symmetries. Noûs 32: 231–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2003. Bigger than chaos: Understanding complexity through probability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2005. How are the sciences of complex systems possible? Philosophy of Science 72(4): 531–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2008. Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2011. Probability out of determinism. In Probabilities in physics, eds. Claus Beisbart and Stephann Hartmann, Chapter 13, 339–364. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Téglás, E., V. Girotto, M. Gonzalez, and L. L. Bonatti. 2007. Intuitions of probabilities shape expectations about the future at 12 months and beyond. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104(48): 19156–19159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Kries, J. 1886. Die Principien der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung. Mohr Siebeck.

  • von Plato, J. 1994. Creating modern probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Werndl, C. 2010. The simple behaviour of complex systems explained? Review of “Bigger than chaos, understanding complexity through probability”. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61(4): 875–882.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu, F., and S. Denison. 2009. Statistical inference and sensitivity to sampling in 11-month-old infants. Cognition 112(1): 97–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu, F., and V. Garcia. 2008. Intuitive statistics by 8-month-old infants. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 105: 5012–5015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marshall Abrams.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abrams, M., Eberhardt, F. & Strevens, M. Equidynamics and reliable reasoning about frequencies. Metascience 24, 173–188 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-014-9971-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-014-9971-y

Navigation