Skip to main content
Log in

Process as reality: Kierkegaard’s aesthetic approach to the ethical

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper makes the point that Kierkegaard’s ideas concerning individuality cannot be understood clearly without placing them in the context of what I am calling ontological isolation. This means the radical deprivation by selfhood of every aspect of reality, to the point where not even the possibility or illusion of reality is available to the self. In this context the self is required to become itself, forming itself in and out of its own absolute nothingness, ontological destitution, or wrongness. With this form of isolation as our investigative key, we unlock what Kierkegaard means by his command to become a self, where becoming itself, in absence of prior possibility, constitutes the reality of self, and why Kierkegaard places crucial emphasis, contrary to the tradition, on the priority of negativity. By having the self originate itself in “absolute difficulty,” or that wherein the act itself, or pure doing without result, is primary, Kierkegaard now replaces metaphysics with ethics in order of priority, and places the self inseparably in a world that responds directly to that act. I show here a parallel between Kierkegaard’s approach to ethical action with that of artistic creation of a kind of world, the work of art. In doing so I reveal the inadequacy of interpretations that would impose traditional forms of isolation, social and cosmic, on Kierkegaard, as some of his critics do, or that would place Kierkegaard’s ethics within traditional developmental models, as many of his sympathizers do.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 116).

  2. For example, see MacIntyre (1981).

  3. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 116).

  4. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 135).

  5. MacIntyre (1981, p. 41).

  6. Mackey (1972, p. 279).

  7. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 280).

  8. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 133).

  9. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 187).

  10. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 80).

  11. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 80).

  12. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 272n).

  13. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 177).

  14. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 80).

  15. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 76).

  16. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 277).

  17. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 80).

  18. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 277).

  19. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 143).

  20. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 77).

  21. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 20).

  22. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 80n).

  23. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 4, p. 120).

  24. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 147).

  25. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 199).

  26. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 186).

  27. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 421).

  28. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 467).

  29. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 412).

  30. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 387).

  31. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 78).

  32. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 75).

  33. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 75).

  34. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 178).

  35. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 84).

  36. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 68).

  37. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 257).

  38. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 151).

  39. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 177).

  40. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 315).

  41. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 385).

  42. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 533).

  43. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 306).

  44. Kierkegaard, (1941, p. 78).

  45. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 148).

  46. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 414).

  47. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 74n).

  48. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 281).

  49. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 387).

  50. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 146).

  51. Kierkegaard (1962, p. 121).

  52. See Kierkegaard (1943, pp. 35–55).

  53. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 63).

  54. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 63).

  55. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 216).

  56. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 52).

  57. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 1, p. 463).

  58. Rudd (1993, p. 118). See also Davenport (2001, pp. 265–323) for a defense of the developmental model. Here Davenport fails to recognize the significance of absolute difficulty and of ontological isolation in Kierkegaard, and so gives us a virtue-model of self that is not, after all, as “existential” as it is Aristotelian and Thomistic. For a more recent developmental interpretation, see Fremstedal (2014, pp. 58ff).

  59. Rudd (1993, p. 118).

  60. Kierkegaard (1971, vol. 2, p. 267).

  61. See, for example, Fremstedal (2014, pp. 29ff), wherein sin involves a duality of a given, not destroyed, self; see also ibid., p. 194, for a dualistic relation of self to world, rather than that of a self integrated in world, as self positively creates itself in the negativity of ontological isolation.

  62. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 306).

  63. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 322).

  64. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 110, his emphasis).

  65. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 20).

  66. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 38).

  67. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 162).

  68. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 60).

  69. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 69).

  70. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 67).

  71. Kierkegaard (1968a, p. 123, his emphasis).

  72. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 38).

  73. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 15).

  74. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 20).

  75. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 116).

  76. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 146).

  77. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 61).

  78. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 100).

  79. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 42).

  80. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 42).

  81. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 38).

  82. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 99n).

  83. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 17).

  84. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 2, p. 4).

  85. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 17).

  86. See Kierkegaard (1941, p. 173).

  87. See Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 1, p. 456).

  88. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 4, pp. 351–352).

  89. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 171).

  90. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 424).

  91. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 78).

  92. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 38).

  93. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 3, p. 417).

  94. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 3, p. 318).

  95. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 473, his emphasis).

  96. Kierkegaard (1944, p. 74).

  97. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 538).

  98. Beckett (1965, p. 103).

  99. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 414).

  100. Plath (1983, p. 248).

  101. Solomon (1987, p. 240).

  102. Naifte and Smith (1991, p. 661).

  103. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 1, p. 463).

  104. See Kierkegaard (1944, p. 127).

  105. See Kierkegaard (1941, p. 388).

  106. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 425).

  107. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 52).

  108. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 424).

  109. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 424).

  110. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 148).

  111. Kierkegaard (1956, p. 216).

  112. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 482).

  113. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 38).

  114. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 1, p. 24).

  115. Plath (1983, p. 312).

  116. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 27).

  117. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 36).

  118. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 116).

  119. See Kierkegaard (1941, pp. 390ff).

  120. See Davenport (2001, p. 273). See also Hannay (1982, p. 210).

  121. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 36).

  122. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 36).

  123. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 27).

  124. Kierkegaard, (1968b, p. 39).

  125. Plath (1983, p. 236).

  126. Kierkegaard (1968c, p. 179).

  127. Wittgenstein (1958, p. 161).

  128. Wittgenstein (1958, p. 161).

  129. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 31).

  130. Kierkegaard (1968b, p. 48).

  131. Kierkegaard (1971, vol. 1, p. 305).

  132. Plath (1983, p. 192).

  133. Kierkegaard (1967–1975, vol. 4, p. 487).

  134. For a view of Kierkegaard that accepts what it takes to be the subjectivism of Kierkegaard’s idea of truth, while denying that this makes truth to be arbitrary, see Caputo (2007). Here Caputo overlooks the centrality of absolute difficulty in Kierkegaard, focusing instead on a private form of “lived experience” in a given subject. For a similar view, see Mehl (2001).

  135. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 37).

  136. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 305).

  137. Kierkegaard (1971, vol. 2, p. 98).

  138. Kierkegaard (1971, vol. 2, p. 280).

  139. Kierkegaard (1941, p. 270).

References

  • Beckett, Samuel. 1965. Proust: Three dialogues with Georges Duthuit. London: Calderbooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, John D. 2007. How to read Kierkegaard. London: Granta Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davenport, John J. 2001. Toward an existential virtue ethics: Kierkegaard and MacIntyre. In Kierkegaard after MacIntyre, ed. John J. Davenport and Anthony Rudd. Chicago: Open Court.

  • Fremstedal, Roe. 2014. Kierkegaard and Kant on radical evil and the highest good. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Hannay, Alastair. 1982. Kierkegaard. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1941. Concluding unscientific postscript (trans: Swenson, D. and Lowrie, W.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1943. Every good and every perfect gift is from above. In Edifying discourses (trans: Swenson, D. F. and Swenson, L. M.). Minneapolis: Augsburg Publishing House.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1944. The concept of dread (trans: Lowrie, W.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1956. Purity of heart is to will one thing (trans: Steele, D.). New York: Harper Perrenial.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1962. The works of love (trans: Hong, H. and Hong, E.). New York: Harper and Row.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1967–1975. Journals and papers (trans: Hong, H. and Hong, E.), 4 vols. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1968a. Judge for yourselves! In For self-examination and judge for yourselves!(trans: Lowrie, W.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1968b. Fear and trembling. In Fear and trembling and the sickness unto death (trans: Lowrie, W.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1968c. The sickness unto death. In Fear and trembling and the sickness unto death (trans: Lowrie, W.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kierkegaard, Soren. 1971. Either/Or (trans: Lowrie, W.), 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • MacIntyre, Alisdaire. 1981. After virtue: A study in moral theory. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackey, Louis. 1972. The loss of the world in Kierkegaard’s ethics. In Kierkegaard, a collection of critical essays, ed. Josiah Thompson. Doubleday and Co: Garden City, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehl, Peter J. 2001. Kierkegaard and the relativist challenge to practical philosophy. In Kierkegaard after MacIntyre, ed. John J. Davenport and Anthony Rudd. Chicago: Open Court.

  • Naifte, Steven, and Gregory White Smith. 1991. Jackson Pollock, an American saga. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plath, Sylvia. 1983. The journals of Sylvia Plath, ed. Ted Hughes and Frances McCullough. New York: Ballantine Books.

  • Rudd, Anthony. 1993. Kierkegaard and the limits of the ethical. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Deborah. 1987. Jackson Pollock, a biography. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958 (trans: Anscombe, G.E.M.). New York: Macmillan Company.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael J. Matthis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Matthis, M.J. Process as reality: Kierkegaard’s aesthetic approach to the ethical. Cont Philos Rev 51, 23–41 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-016-9409-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-016-9409-x

Keywords

Navigation