Skip to main content
Log in

Bridging Ranking Theory and the Stability Theory of Belief

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we compare Leitgeb’s stability theory of belief (Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 164:1338-1389, 2013; The Philosophical Review, 123:131-171, [2014]) and Spohn’s ranking-theoretic account of belief (Spohn, 1988, 2012). We discuss the two theories as solutions to the lottery paradox. To compare the two theories, we introduce a novel translation between ranking (mass) functions and probability (mass) functions. We draw some crucial consequences from this translation, in particular a new probabilistic belief notion. Based on this, we explore the logical relation between the two belief theories, showing that models of Leitgeb’s theory correspond to certain models of Spohn’s theory. The reverse is not true (or holds only under special constraints on the parameter of the translation). Finally, we discuss how these results raise new questions in belief theory. In particular, we raise the question whether stability (a key ingredient of Leitgeb’s theory) is rightly thought of as a property pertaining to belief (rather than to knowledge).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘if and only if’.

  2. We keep the number “4”, in “(B4)”, in correspondence to the enumeration of the defining properties of a proper filter (cf. Definition 6), i.e. (1) non-empty, (2) proper, (3) upwards closed and (4) closed under finite intersections. This is condition (b) in [15, def. 4.5].

  3. A third solution is to choose a particular non-uniform probability assignment.

  4. For the definitions in this section see [15, ch. 5].

  5. This is clear for minimum and maximum. For minimativity it follows from the De Morgan law \(\overline {A \cup B} = \overline {A} \cap \overline {B}\).

  6. The lottery paradox may of course be circumvented by dropping (B4).

  7. Leitgeb also weakens “ >” to “ ≥”. This is irrelevant in the finite case, when t=1 is excluded.

  8. Note that the Lockean thesis already implies (B1 – 3) by the axioms of probability.

  9. Cf. [5]. In terms of Leitgeb’s [3] more general definition of P-stability, this is P-stability\(_{\frac {1}{2}}\).

  10. Leitgeb shows a slightly different, but equivalent, result: Let B be a predicate over the algebra \(\mathcal {A}\) and P a function over \(\mathcal {A}\) with values in [0,1]. Then (a,b,c) is equivalent to (b, d), with letters referring to the following assumptions: (a) B is a core belief notion, with core C B , (b) P is a probability, (c) together they satisfy the Lockean thesis for t = P(C B ), (d) there is a unique non-empty C = C B such that (2) of Theorem 1. We chose the presentation in Theorem 1 for the following reasons, it is simpler and outsources two hypothesis: (b) and (a’) that B is a belief operator. (b) figures in both equivalent statements of Leitgeb and (a’) on a finite algebra is equivalent to (a).

  11. In the sense of the Lebesgue measure on the probability hypersurface.

  12. This is due to the fact that Φ a induces a bijection between \(\mathbb {K}^{n}:=\{\mathbf {k} \in (\mathbb {R}^{+}_{\infty })^{n}\colon \exists i <n,\; k_{i} =0\}\) and \(\mathbb {P}^{n}:=\{\mathbf {p} \in [0,1]^{n}\colon \sum p_{i} =1\}\).

  13. This parallelism differs from the parallelism proposed by Pearl to explain the parallelism of the operations (\((\min , +, -)\) v.s. (+,×,÷)). The later is based on equating algebraic rank values with the standard part of a logarithm to an infinitesimal base of a non-standard probability: \(\kappa (A)=\text {st} \log _{i} P(A)\) – see [15, Theorem 10.1].

  14. However, see [7, equation 17], and [6]. We became aware of this work after having developed atomic probabilistic belief as a probabilistic analogue to ranking-theoretic belief. The odds-threshold rule formulated by Lin–Kelly amounts to believing a proposition A iff it is implied by the disjunction of the most plausible propositions of a partition (C j ) jJ . The most plausible C i ’s are those that score not below a certain fraction of the most probable C j , i.e. \(P(C_{i}) \geq \max _{j \in J} P(C_{j})/ x\), where x might be a function of i. For fixed x the odds-threshold rule determines an atomic probabilistic belief model with threshold \(y= \max _{j \in J} P(C_{j})/x\).

  15. By ‘factual assumption’ something stronger than ‘supposing for the sake of the argument’ is meant. Factual assumptions are assumptions about facts which the agent is willing to rely on in her practical and theoretical reasoning – the agent uses them as a basis of her actions and for further inquiries.

  16. In choosing to theorise about the individual context of reasoning of the rational agent who has the beliefs (as opposed to focusing on the intersubjective context of ascribing beliefs), we take Leitgeb [5, p. 25] to be following this order of explanation.

  17. Yet, as Greene [2, ch. 11] carefully argues, there may be some propitious circumstances under which versions of the multiverse hypothesis would turn out to have testable consequences.

  18. This problem carries over to attempts of using Leitgeb’s stability thesis as part of an account of knowledge (unless, of course, the latter can be explicated in terms of ranking theory in a way that satisfies the principle of invariance).

  19. One particular concern is the problem of logical omniscience. Yalcin [17, 18] has argued that introducing partition-sensitivity of belief makes our models of rational belief less idealised. In the present dialectic this would count as an argument in favour of Leitgeb’s stability theory against ranking theory. In [13] a different solution to the problem of logical omniscience was presented, which would require reinterpreting the regulatory norms of ranking theory as providing norms of public, argumentative discourse instead of norms of individual belief.

References

  1. Dubois, D., & Prade, H. (1988). Possibility Theory: An Approach to Computerized Processing of Uncertainty. New York: Plenum Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Greene, B. (2012). The Hidden Reality: Parallel Universes and the Deep Laws of the Cosmos. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Leitgeb, H. (2013). Reducing Belief Simpliciter to Degrees of Belief. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 164(12), 1338–1389. doi:http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2013.06.015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Leitgeb, H. (2014). The Stability Theory of Belief. The Philosophical Review, 123(2), 131–171. doi:10.1215/00318108-2400575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Leitgeb, H. (2015). The Humean Thesis on Belief. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 89(1), 143–185. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8349.2015.00248.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Levi, I. (1996). For the Sake of the Argument: Ramsey Test Conditionals, Inductive Inference and Non-monotonic Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. Lin, H., & Kelly, K.T. (2012). Propositional Reasoning that Tracks Probabilistic Reasoning. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 957–981. doi:10.1007/s10992-012-9237-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Raidl, E. (2014). Probabilité, Invariance et Objectivité, PhD thesis at the University of Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne, IHPST. http://www.theses.fr/s123429.

  9. Rott, H. (2004). Stability, strength and sensitivity: Converting belief into knowledge. Erkenntnis, 61(2-3), 469–93. doi:10.1007/s10670-004-9287-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Rott, H. (2009). Degrees all the way down: Beliefs, non-beliefs and disbeliefs. In Huber, F., & Schmidt-Petri, C. (Eds.) Degrees of Belief (pp. 301–339). Dordrecht: Springer.

  11. Rott, H. (2015a). Stability and scepticism in the generation of plain beliefs from probabilities. Manuscript version of May 26, 2015.

  12. Rott, H. (2015b). Unstable knowledge, unstable belief. Manuscript version of July 28, 2015.

  13. Skovgaard-Olsen, N. (2015). The problem of logical Omniscience, the preface paradox, and doxastic commitments. Synthese, 1–26. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0979-7.

  14. Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal Conditional Functions. A Dynamic Theory of Epistemic States. In Harper, W.L., & Skyrms, B. (Eds.) Causation in Decision, Belief Change, and Statistics, Vol. 2 (pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  15. Spohn, W. (2012). The Laws of Belief: Ranking Theory and its Philosophical Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. Spohn, W. (presentation). The Value of Knowledge. https://www.tilburguniversity.edu/upload/87af9554-bf5f-4514-be46-021183a63bf0_Presentation%20Spohn.pdf. Accessed 3 March 2015.

  17. Yalcin, S. (2011). Nonfactualism about Epistemic Modality. In Egan, A., Weatherson, B., & Yalcin, S (Eds.) (pp. 295–332): Oxford University Press.

  18. Yalcin, S. (forthcoming). Belief as Question-Sensitive. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://www.academia.edu/26580337/Belief_as_Question-Sensitive. Accessed 19 August 2016.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Hannes Leitgeb for his helpful comments on an earlier manuscript, Hans Rott for his suggestions and critical remarks and an anonymous referee for pressing us to focus more on the novelty of the translation and its consequences. They all helped to improve the quality of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Raidl.

Additional information

Eric Raidl’s work was supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) Research Unit FOR 1614. Niels Skovgaard-Olsen’s work was supported by a grant to Wolfgang Spohn from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) as part of the priority program New Frameworks of Rationality (SPP 1516).

Appendix A: Proofs

Appendix A: Proofs

1.1 A.1 Prerequisites

Lemma 5 (cf. lemma 2)

Let P be a probability over a finite algebra \(\mathcal {A}=\wp ({\Omega })\) . If P(A)≠1, then the following are equivalent:

  1. 1.

    \(A \in \mathcal {A}\) is P-stable,

  2. 2.

    \(\forall w \in A, P(w) > P(\overline {A})\),

  3. 3.

    \(\min _{A} P(w) > P(\overline {A})\),

  4. 4.

    For all non-empty \(D \subseteq A\) and all \(E \subseteq \overline {A}\) , P(D)>P(E).

If P(A)=1 these equivalences hold, with > replaced by ≥.

Proof

First assume P(A)≠1.

\((1 \Rightarrow 2)\) :

Let \(A \in \mathcal {A}\) be P-stable. If A = then (2) is vacuously satisfied. Suppose A. Let wA and \(B = \{w\} \cup \overline {A}\), so that \(B \cap A= \{w\} \neq \emptyset \). P(B)=0 is impossible, since then P(w)=0 and \(P(\overline {A})= 0\), contradicting P(A)≠1. Therefore P(B)>0. Thus the stability condition applies and \(P(A|B)> \frac {1}{2}\). Therefore the following are equivalent:

$$ P(A|B) = \frac{P(A \cap B)}{P(B)} = \frac{P(w)}{P(w) + P(\overline{A})} > \frac{1}{2} $$
(A.1)
$$ P(w) > \frac{1}{2}(P(w) + P(\overline{A})) $$
(A.2)
$$ \frac{1}{2}P(w) > \frac{1}{2}P(\overline{A}) $$
(A.3)
$$ P(w) > P(\overline{A}) $$
(A.4)
\((2 \Rightarrow 3)\) :

If Eq. A.4 holds for all wA then it holds for wA s.t. P(w) is minimal.

\((3 \Rightarrow 4)\) :

Let \(p_{A} = \min _{A} P(w) > P(\overline {A})\). Consider \(\emptyset \neq D \subseteq A\) and \(E \subseteq \overline {A}\). By sub-addivity and minimality:

$$ P(D) \geq p_{A} > P(\overline{A}) \geq P(E) $$
(A.5)
\((4 \Rightarrow 1)\) :

If A = , then A is vacuously P-stable. Let us therefore consider A. Let \(B \in \mathcal {A}\), such that \(B \cap A \neq \emptyset \) and P(B)>0. Define \(D = B \cap A\) and E = B D. We have \(\emptyset \neq D \subseteq A\) and \(E \subseteq \overline {A}\). So that (4) applies and we have the following equivalent expressions

$$ P(D) > P(E) $$
(A.6)
$$ \frac{1}{2} P(D) > \frac{1}{2} P(E) $$
(A.7)
$$ P(D) - \frac{1}{2} P(D) > \frac{1}{2} P(E) $$
(A.8)
$$ P(D) > \frac{1}{2} (P(E) +P(D)) $$
(A.9)
$$ \frac{P(D)}{P(D) + P(E)} > \frac{1}{2} $$
(A.10)
$$ P(A|B) > \frac{1}{2} $$
(A.11)

If P(A)=1, then in \((1 \Rightarrow 2)\) P(B)=0 is possible, yielding \(P(w) \geq P(\overline {A})=0\) for wA. This weak inequality transfers to (3) and (4). \((4 \Rightarrow 1)\) since P(D)≥P(E)=0 (4). Thus \(P(A|B) = \frac {P(D)}{P(D) + P(E)} =1> \frac {1}{2}\). □

Proof Proof 2 of Theorem 1

Assume \(\mathcal {A}=\wp ({\Omega })\) (finite), B a belief operator (with core C) and P a probability function over \(\mathcal {A}\).

\((1) \Rightarrow (2)\) :

Suppose B,P satisfy the Lockean thesis, for t = P(C).

  1. i

    To derive a contradiction, suppose that C is not P-stable. Therefore there is vC such that \(P(v) \leq P(\overline {C}) = 1- P(C)\) (Lemma 5.2 or even \(P(v) < P(\overline {C})=0\) if P(C)=1 creating an immediate contradiction). Consider \(B=\overline {C} \cup (C \setminus \{v\})\) which is not a superset of C. Therefore it is not believed. Yet, P(B)=1−P(v)≥P(C) = t, contradicting the Lockean thesis.

  2. ii

    To derive a contradiction, suppose P(C)=1, and that there is \(D \subsetneq C\) with P(D)=1. Then the Lockean thesis implies B(D), therefore C is not the core.

\((2) \Rightarrow (1)\).:

Suppose (i) C is P-stable and (ii) if P(C)=1 then C is the smallest probability-1 set. Then \(t:=P(C) = P(C|{\Omega })>\frac {1}{2}\) (since C). Let us show that (i,ii) imply the Lockean thesis. \(C \subseteq A\) implies P(A)≥t (sub-additivity). Therefore B(A) implies P(A)≥t. Let us show the reverse.

Suppose there is B such that ¬B(B) and P(B)≥t (contradicting the Lockean thesis). Then \(C \nsubseteq B\). There are three cases: (1) \(B \subsetneq C\), (2) \(B \cap C = \emptyset \) or (3) \(\emptyset \neq B \cap C \notin \{C,B\}\). All lead to a contradiction. If (1) \(B \subsetneq C\) then, by sub-additivity P(B)≤P(C) = t. P(B)<P(C) would contradict P(B)≥t. P(B) = P(C) would contradict ¬B(B). (2) is excluded because if \(P(B)\geq t > \frac {1}{2}\), P(C) = t and \(B \cap C = \emptyset \), then \(P(B \cup C) \geq 2t >1\). Consider (3). Let \(D= C \cap B \subseteq C\) and \(E = B \setminus D \subseteq \overline {C}\). By construction and hypothesis P(B) = P(D) + P(E)≥t = P(C). Define \(B^{\prime } = D \cup \overline {C}\). \(B^{\prime }\supseteq B\), therefore \(P(B^{\prime }) \geq P(B)\). Take a superset \(D^{\prime }\) of D, such that \(D^{\prime } = C \setminus \{w\}\) with wC (which exists because \(D=B \cap C \neq C\) by (3). Define \(B^{\prime \prime } = D^{\prime } \cup \overline {C}\), therefore \(B^{\prime } \subseteq B^{\prime \prime }\). Then \(P(C) =t\leq P(B) \leq P(B^{\prime }) \leq P(B^{\prime \prime }) = 1 - P(w)\). Which implies \(P(w) \leq P(\overline {C})\). This contradicts (i) P-stability of C (Lemma 5.2) if P(C)≠1. If P(C)=1, then \(P(w) = P(\overline {C})=0\) could be possible, but then C is not the smallest probability 1 set, contradicting (ii).

Proof Proof 3 of Lemma 3

Let a∈(0,1).

  1. 1.

    Let κ(w) be a ranking mass. Then \(P^{a}_{\kappa }(w)\) is a probability mass: Its sum is 1 by the normalisation constant, and all \(P^{a}_{\kappa }(w) \geq 0\). Since 0≤a κ(w) for a∈(0,1).

  2. 2.

    Let P(w) be a probability mass. Then \({\kappa ^{a}_{P}}(w)\) is a ranking mass: Let \(p=\max _{v \in {\Omega }} P(v)\) (which exists, since Ω is finite). Set r w = P(w)/p for w∈Ω. Then r w ∈[0,1]. Thus \(\ln r_{w} \in [-\infty , 0]\). Yet, for a∈(0,1), we have \(\ln a \in (-\infty , 0)\). Therefore \({\kappa ^{a}_{P}}(w) = \log _{a} r_{w} = \frac {\ln r_{w}}{\ln a} \geq 0\). \({\kappa ^{a}_{P}}\) has a zero for w∈Ω such that P(w) = p. Since then r w =1 and \(\ln r_{w} = \ln 1 =0\).

  3. 3.

    Because Ψ a Φ a (κ) = κ and Φ a Ψ a (P) = P.

    $$ \kappa^{a}_{P^{a}_{\kappa}}(w) = \log_{a} \frac{P^{a}_{\kappa}(w)}{\max_{\Omega} P^{a}_{\kappa}(v)} = \log_{a} \frac{a^{\kappa(w)}}{\max_{\Omega} a^{\kappa(v)}} = \log_{a} \frac{a^{\kappa(w)}}{a^{0}} = \kappa(w) $$
    (A.12)
    $$P^{a}_{{\kappa^{a}_{P}}}(w) = \frac{a^{{\kappa^{a}_{P}}(w)}}{Z} =\frac{a^{\log_{a} \frac{P(w)}{\max_{\Omega} P(v)}}}{Z} =\frac{ P(w)}{\max_{\Omega} P(v) {\sum}_{u \in {\Omega}} \frac{P(u)}{\max_{\Omega} P(v)}} = P(w) $$
    (A.13)
  4. 4.

    For a∈(0,1), a x and \(\log _{a} y\) are strictly decreasing.

1.2 A.2 Belief Models

Proof Proof 4 of Theorem 2

Let a∈(0,1).

  1. 1.

    Let (B,κ) be a Spohn belief. Since κ is a ranking function, \(P={P^{a}_{K}}\) is a probability function for any a∈(0,1) (Lemma 3.1). It therefore suffices to show that [≥y] P is the core of B for y: = a z/Z(a). Note that κ(w)≤z iff P(w)≥y (Lemma 3.4). Therefore for all \(A \in \mathcal {A}\):

    $$\begin{array}{rcl} A \in \mathcal{B}& \text{ iff} & \kappa(\overline{A})>z\\ &&\\ & \text{ iff} & [\leq z]_{\kappa} \subseteq A\\ &&\\ & \text{ iff} & [\geq y]_{P} \subseteq A\\ \end{array} $$

    Therefore \(\mathcal {B}:=\{A \in \mathcal {A}: \mathbf {B}(A)\}\) is generated by [≥y] P (non-empty). Thus \(\mathcal {B}\) is a principal filter. Yet, a principal filter is generated by a unique element (its core). Therefore [≤y] P is the core.

  2. 2.

    By the fact that \({\Psi }_{a} = {\Phi }^{-1}_{a}\) (Lemma 3.3).

Proof Proof 5 of Theorem 3

Assume (B,P) is an atomic probabilistic belief model over a finite algebra \(\mathcal {A} = \wp ({\Omega })\). Therefore P is a probability and B is a belief operator over \(\mathcal {A}\). Additionally B has a unique core, namely C=[≥y] P for some y∈[0,1].

  • (⇒)  Suppose (B,P) is a Leitgeb model. In particular, (B,P) satisfy the Lockean thesis, for t = P(C) with C the core. Therefore, by Theorem 1 (\(1 \Rightarrow 2\)), (i) C is P-stable and (ii) if P(C)=1 then C is the smallest probability-1 set. Set \(y= \min _{C} P(w)\). Then \(y > P(\overline {C})\) by Lemma 5.2 and P-stability of C, if P(C)≠1. If P(C)=1, then C is the smallest probability 1 set and therefore \(y>0 = P(\overline {C})\).

  • (⇐)  Suppose that the core C of the atomic belief model (B,P) satisfies \(y>P(\overline {C})\), for y the atomic threshold. It suffices to show that the Lockean thesis is satisfied for t C = P(C). Let t C = P(C). Then it suffices to show that q<t C for \(q = \max \{P(A): \neg \mathbf {B}(A)\}\). Because we may then always chose t with q<t<t C such that the Lockean thesis is satisfied. By finiteness q exists. A non-believed element with maximal probability will have the form \(A = \overline {C} \cup C \setminus \{w\}\), where wC has minimal probability in C. Yet, by the separation assumption \(P(w) \geq y > P(\overline {C})\). This implies \(0 > P(\overline {C}) - P(w)\) which implies \(P(C) > P(\overline {C}) + P(C) - P(w)\), which implies t C = P(C)>P(A) = q.

Proof Proof 6 of Corollary 1

Let a∈(0,1).

  1. 1.

    In a Leitgeb belief model, B is a belief operator. B is closed under conjunction by assumption and B satisfies (B1-3) by the Lockean thesis. Additionally, the core C is P-stable and if P(C)=1, then it is the smallest probability 1 set. Therefore \(\min _{C} P(w) > P(\overline {C})\). Therefore \(y=\min _{C} P(w)\) can be chosen as atomic threshold. Therefore a Leitgeb belief model is always an atomic belief model. Thus the claim follows from Theorems 2.2 and 3.

  2. 2.

    Let (B,κ) be a Spohn belief model with core C and \(z = \max _{C} \kappa (w)\) and \(x = \min _{\overline {C}} \kappa (w)\). Let a∈(0,1). Then \((\mathbf {B}, P^{a}_{\kappa })\) is an atomic belief model, with

    $$ y(a,z) = \frac{a^{z}}{Z(a)} $$
    (A.14)

    by Theorem 2.1. This model is a Leitgeb model iff \(y(a,z)>P(\overline {C})\) (Theorem 3). This holds iff \(a^{z} > Z(\overline {C}) :={\sum }_{\overline {C}} a^{\kappa (w)}\). It therefore suffices to show this later inequality. Assume

    $$ a >|\overline{C}|^{\frac{1}{z-x}} = \left( e^{\ln |\overline{C}|}\right)^{1/(z-x)} = e^{\frac{\ln |\overline{C}|}{z-x}} $$
    (A.15)

    The following conditions are equivalent:

    $$\ln a> \frac{ \ln |\overline{C}|}{(z-x)} $$
    (A.16)
    $$(z-x)\ln a> \ln |\overline{C}| $$
    (A.17)
    $$a^{z-x}> |\overline{C}| $$
    (A.18)
    $$ a^{z} > |\overline{C}| a^{x} = \sum\limits_{\overline{C}} a^{x} $$
    (A.19)

    Therefore \(a^{z} > {\sum_{\overline {C}} a^{x} \geq Z(\overline {C})}\), since \(x = \min _{\overline {C}} \kappa (w)\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Raidl, E., Skovgaard-Olsen, N. Bridging Ranking Theory and the Stability Theory of Belief. J Philos Logic 46, 577–609 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-016-9411-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-016-9411-0

Keywords

Navigation