Skip to main content
Log in

Inter-Definability of Horn Contraction and Horn Revision

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There have been a number of publications in recent years on generalising the AGM paradigm to the Horn fragment of propositional logic. Most of them focused on adapting AGM contraction and revision to the Horn setting. It remains an open question whether the adapted Horn contraction and Horn revision are inter-definable as in the AGM case through the Levi and Harper identities. In this paper, we give a positive answer by providing methods for generating contraction and revision from their dual operations. Noticeably, we cannot apply the Levi and Harper identities directly in such methods as the Horn fragment does not fully support negation. To overcome this difficulty, a Horn approximation technique called Horn strengthening is used. We show that Horn contraction generated from Horn revision is always plausible whereas Horn revision generated from Horn contraction is, in general, implausible and, to regain plausibility, the generating contraction has to be properly restricted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Levi’s actual proposal is more general but this form has been adopted for the AGM paradigm.

  2. The expansion function + takes a belief set K and a formula ϕ and returns the logical closure of their union.

  3. We refer to AGM revision (contraction) functions as those that satisfy the full set of AGM revision (contraction) postulates.

  4. In Katsuno and Mendelzon [21], a belief set is represented as a formula and faithfulness is a condition for the assignment of pre-orders to formulas. An assignment is faithful if logically equivalent formulas are assigned the identical pre-order and for any formula ϕ, its assigned pre-order ≼ is such that m i n(Ω,≼) = |ϕ|. Here we work with a belief set directly, which is the same as working with formulas since the language \(\mathcal {L}\) is finite. Also, we use faithfulness as a condition on the pre-orders to simplify the presentation.

  5. For uniformity with the terminology in this paper, we name the Horn revision differently to Delgrande and Peppas [9].

  6. Disjunctive Elimination was originally proposed in the context of belief base change where the the agent’s set of beliefs are not necessarily logically closed. It is adapted to belief set change here where the set of beliefs are assumed to be logically closed.

  7. The representation theorem for TRPMHC is given by Zhang and Pagnucco [34]. TRPMHC can be characterised by \((H\dot {-} 1)\)\((H\dot {-} 4)\), \((H\dot {-} de)\), \((H\dot {-} 6)\) , \((H\dot {-} pa)\) , and \((H\dot {-} 8)\). It was subsequently determined that the proof for this theorem was not valid as it contains a subtle error. The correct part of the proof assures that a TRPMHC function satisfies \((H\dot {-} 1)\)\((H\dot {-} 4)\), \((H\dot {-} de)\), \((H\dot {-} 6)\), \((H\dot {-} pa)\), and \((H\dot {-} 8)\).

  8. The simple derivation methods can be found in the proof of Theorem 4.

  9. Note that for a pre-order of interpretations the minimally ordered interpretations are most preferred whereas for an (Horn) epistemic entrenchment the maximally ordered formulas are most preferred.

  10. Such preference over formulas is also used by Boutilier [6] under the name of degree of surprise.

References

  1. Adaricheva, K., Sloan, R.H., & Szörényi, B. (2012). Horn belief contraction: remainders, envelopes and complexity. In Proceedings of the 13th international conference on principles of knowledge representation and reasoning (KR-2012), pp. 107–115.

  2. Alchourrón, C.E., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions. J Symb Log, 50(2), 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Booth, R., Meyer, T., & Varzinczak, I.J. (2009). Next steps in propositional Horn contraction. In Proceedings of the 21st international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI-2009), pp. 702–707.

  4. Booth, R., Meyer, T., Varzinczak, I.J., & Wassermann, R. (2010). Horn belief change: a contraction core. In Proceedings of the 20th european conference on artificial intelligence (ECAI-2011), pp. 1065–1066.

  5. Booth, R., Meyer, T., Varzinczak, I.J., & Wassermann, R. (2011). On the link between partial meet, kernel, and infra contraction and its application to Horn logic. J Artif Intell Res, 42, 31–53.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Boutilier, C. (1995). On the revision of probabilistic belief states. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 36.

  7. Darwiche, A., & Pearl, J. (1996). On the logic of iterated belief revision. Artif Intell, 89, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Delgrande, J.P. (2008). Horn clause belief change: Contraction functions. In Proceedings of the 11th international conference on principles of knowledge representation and reasoning (KR-2008), pp. 156–165.

  9. Delgrande, J.P., & Peppas, P. (2011). Revising Horn theories. In Proceedings of the 22nd international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI-2011), pp. 839–844.

  10. Delgrande, J.P., & Peppas, P. (2015). Belief revision in Horn theories. Artif Intell, 218, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Delgrande, J.P., & Wassermann, R. (2010). Horn clause contraction function: Belief set and belief base approaches. In Proceedings of the 12th international conference on principles of knowledge representation and reasoning (KR-2010), pp. 143–152.

  12. Delgrande, J.P., & Wassermann, R. (2013). Horn clause contraction functions. J Artif Intell Res, 48, 475–551.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Fermé, E., Krevneris, M., & Reis, M. (2008). An axiomatic characterization of ensconcement-based contraction. J Log Comput, 18(5), 739–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Fuhrmann, A., & Hansson, S.O. (1994). A survey of multiple contractions. J Log Lang Inf, 3(1), 39–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux: Modelling the dynamics of epistemic states MIT press.

  16. Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1988). Revisions of knowledge systems using epistemic entrenchment. In Proceedings of the 2nd conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge (TARK-1988), pp. 83–95.

  17. Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. J Philos Log, 17(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Hansson, S.O. (1999). A textbook of belief dynamics theory change and database updating kluwer.

  19. Hansson, S.O. (2010). Multiple and iterated contraction reduced to single-step single-sentence contraction. Synthese, 173, 153–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Harper, W. (1975). Rational concept change. In Proceedings of the meeting of the philosophy of science association, pp. 462–494.

  21. Katsuno, H., & Mendelzon, A.O. (1992). Propositional knowledge base revision and minimal change. Artif Intell, 52(3), 263–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Kautz, H., & Selman, B. (1996). Knowledge compilation and theory approximation. J ACM, 43, 193–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Langlois, M., Sloan, R.H., Szörényi, B., & Turán, G. (2008). Horn complements: Towards Horn-to-Horn belief revision. In Proceedings of the 23rd national conference on artificial intelligence (AAAI-2008), pp. 466–471.

  24. Levi, I. (1991). The Fixation of Beliefs and its Udoing Cambridge University Press.

  25. Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals harvard university press.

  26. Meyer, T., Labuschagne, W., & Heidema, J. (2000). Refined epistemic entrenchment. J Log Lang Inf, 9(2), 237–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Nayak, A., Goebel, R., & Orgun, M. (2007). Iterated belief contraction from the first pinciples. In Proc. IJCAI-2007, pp. 2568–2573.

  28. Nayak, A., Goebel, R., Orgun, M., & Pham, T. (2006). Taking Levi identity seriously: A plea for iterated belief contraction. In 1St international conference on knowledge science, engineering and management (KSEM06), pp. 305–317.

  29. Nayak, A.C., Pagnucco, M., & Peppas, P. (2003). Dynamic belief revision operators. Artif Intell, 146, 193–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Ribeiro, M.M., Wassermann, R., Flouris, G., & Antoniou, G. (2013). Minimal change: Relevance and recovery revisited. Artif Intell, 201, 59–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Rott, H. (2006). Shifting priorities: Simple represenations for twenty-seven iterated theory change operators. In H. lagerlund, S. Lindstrom, R. Sliwinski (eds.) Modality matters: Twenty-five eassys in honour of Krister Segerberg, pp. 359–384. Uppsala University Press.

  32. Zhuang, Z., & Pagnucco, M. (2010). Horn contraction via epistemic entrenchment. In Proceedings of the 12th european conference on logics in artificial intelligence (JELIA-2010), pp. 339–351.

  33. Zhuang, Z., & Pagnucco, M. (2010). Two methods of constructing horn contractions. In Proceedings of the 23rd australasian joint conference on artificial intelligence (AI-2010).

  34. Zhuang, Z., & Pagnucco, M. (2011). Transitively relational partial meet horn contraction. In Proceedings of the 22nd international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI-2011), pp. 1132–1138.

  35. Zhuang, Z., & Pagnucco, M. (2012). Model based horn contraction. In Proceedings of the 13th international conference on principles of knowledge representation and reasoning (KR-2012), pp. 169–178.

  36. Zhuang, Z., & Pagnucco, M. (2014). Entrenchment-based Horn contraction. J Artif Intell Res, 51, 227–254.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Zhuang, Z., Pagnucco, M., & Zhang, Y. (2013). Definability of Horn revision from Horn contraction. In Proceedings of the 23rd international joint conference on artificial intelligence (IJCAI-2013), pp. 1205–1211.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Heng Zhang for some fruitful discussions in the early stage of this work and Sebastian Binnewies for proofreading the first draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zhiqiang Zhuang.

Appendix A: Proofs of Results

Appendix A: Proofs of Results

Proof Proof for Lemma 1

  1. 1.

    By model theory H 2H 1 implies |H 1|⊆|H 2|. Again by model theory |H 1|⊆|H 2| implies C n(H 2)⊆C n(H 1). Since H 1 = C n H (H 1) and H 2 = C n H (H 2), C n(H 2)⊆C n(H 1) implies H 2H 1.

  2. 2.

    Immediate from Observation 1.28 in [18].

  3. 3.

    It can be derived from H 1 = C n H (H 1) and H 2 = C n H (H 2) that \(H_{1}\cap H_{2}=\mathcal {H}(Cn(H_{1})\cap Cn(H_{2}))\). By model theory we have |C n(H 1)∩C n(H 2)| = |H 1|∪|H 2|. Then by the Horn closure property we have \(|\mathcal {H}(Cn(H_{1})\cap Cn(H_{2}))|=Cl_{\cap }(|H_{1}|\cup |H_{2}|)\), thus |H 1H 2| = C l (|H 1|∪|H 2|).

  4. 4.5.

    Immediate from the definition of C l .

Proof Proof for Lemma 2

We first show that if ψ is a Horn formula such that ψϕ, then there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\) such that ψχ. If \(\psi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\), then the result trivially holds. Suppose \(\psi \not \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\), then by the definition of Horn strengthening there is \(\chi _{1}\in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\) such that |ψ|⊂|χ 1|⊆|ϕ|. Again, if \(\chi _{1}\not \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\), then there must be \(\chi _{2}\in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\) such that |χ 1|⊂|χ 2|⊆|ϕ|. Since |ϕ| is finite, eventually we will find a χ n which is a Horn strengthening of ϕ. Since |ψ|⊂|χ n |, ψχ n .

Now we show |ϕ| = |χ 1|∪⋯∪|χ n |. |χ 1|∪⋯∪|χ n |⊆|ϕ| follows directly from the definition of Horn strengthening. For the other inclusion, assume there is μ ∈ |ϕ| such that μ∉|χ 1|∪⋯∪|χ n |. Let \(\psi \in \mathcal {L}\) be such that |ψ| = {μ}. Since C l ({μ}) = {μ}, ψ is a Horn formula and |ψ|⊆|ϕ|. Then by the above result there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\) such that |ψ|⊆|χ|. A contradiction ensues. □

Proof for Theorem 2

Suppose \(\dot {-}\) is a MHC function for H with the determining pre-order ≼. \((H\dot {-} 1)\), \((H\dot {-} 2)\), \((H\dot {-} 4)\), and \((H\dot {-} 6)\) follow immediately from the construction of MHC. Let’s show the proof for the rest of the postulates.

\((H\dot {-} 3)\): Suppose ϕH. Then we have |¬ϕ|∩|H|≠. Thus by the faithfulness of ≼ we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆|H|. Thus \(|H\dot {-}\phi |=Cl_{\cap }(min(|\neg \phi |, \preceq )\cup |H|)= Cl_{\cap }(|H|)=|H|\). Then \(H\dot {-}\phi =H\) follows from \((H\dot {-} 1)\).

\((H\dot {-} de)\): We first show that \(\dot {-}\) satisfies the following postulate

$$(H\dot{-} mc) \text{ If } \psi\in H\setminus H\dot{-}\phi, \text{ then }|H\dot{-}\phi|\not\subseteq |\phi\vee\psi|. $$

Suppose \(\psi \in H\setminus H\dot {-}\phi \), it suffices to show there is \(\mu \in |H\dot {-}\phi |\cap |\neg \phi |\) such that μ∉|ψ|. Assume to the contrary that \(|H\dot {-}\phi |\cap |\neg \phi |\subseteq |\psi |\). Then we have, by the construction of MHC, that C l (m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪|H|)∩|¬ϕ|⊆|ψ|. It then follows from m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆|¬ϕ| that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆|ψ|. Since ψH, we have |H|⊆|ψ|. Thus m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪|H|⊆|ψ| which implies C l (m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪|H|)⊆|ψ|. However, it follows from \(\psi \not \in H\dot {-}\phi \), by the construction of MHC that C l (m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪|H|)⫅̸|ψ|. So we have a contradiction and this completes the proof of \((H\dot {-} mc)\).

Now suppose \(\psi \in H\setminus H\dot {-}\phi \). Then it follows from \((H\dot {-} mc)\) that \(|H\dot {-}\phi |\not \subseteq |\phi \vee \psi |\) . Thus there is \(\mu \in |H\dot {-}\phi |\) such that μ∉|ϕψ|. Since |χ|⊆|ϕψ| for all \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\), μ∉|χ| for all \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\) . Then it follows from \(\mu \in |H\dot {-}\phi |\) that \(H\dot {-}\phi \not \vdash \chi \) for all \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\).

\((H\dot {-} 7)\): By the definition of MHC, we have

$$|H\dot{-}\phi\wedge\psi|=Cl_{\cap}(|H|\cup min(|\neg\phi|\cup|\neg\psi|,\preceq))$$

and

$$Cl_{\cap}(|H\dot{-}\phi|\cup|H\dot{-}\psi|)=Cl_{\cap}(|H|\cup min(|\neg\phi|,\preceq)\cup min(|\neg\psi|,\preceq)).$$

It is easy to see that |H| ∪ m i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼)⊆|H| ∪ m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪m i n(|¬ψ|, ≼). Thus \(|H\dot {-}\phi \wedge \psi |\subseteq Cl_{\cap }(|H\dot {-}\phi |\cup |H\dot {-}\psi |)\) which implies \((H\dot {-}\phi )\cap (H\dot {-}\psi ) \subseteq H\dot {-}\phi \wedge \psi \).

\((H\dot {-} 8)\): If ⊩ϕ, ⊩ψ, ϕH or ψH, then \((H\dot {-} 8)\) is trivially satisfied. So suppose ϕ, ψH, ⊯ϕ, and ⊯ψ. Let \(\phi \not \in H\dot {-}\phi \wedge \psi \), we need to show \(H\dot {-} \phi \wedge \psi \subseteq H\dot {-}\phi \). By the construction of MHC, it suffices to show C l (M i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪|H|)⊆C l (m i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼)∪|H|). Since \(\phi \not \in H\dot {-}\phi \wedge \psi \), we have C l (m i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼)∪|H|)⫅̸|ϕ| which implies m i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼)∪|H|⫅̸|ϕ|. Since ϕH, we have |H|⊆|ϕ|. Thus there is μm i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼) such that μ ∈ |¬ϕ|. Then we have for all ν ∈ |¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, μν. Let ωm i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼). It then follows from μ ∈ |¬ϕ|, that ωμ. By the transitivity of ≼, ων follows from ωμ and μν. As ω ∈ |¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, we have ωm i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼). Thus m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆m i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼) which implies C l (m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪|H|)⊆C l (m i n(|¬ϕ| ∪ |¬ψ|, ≼)∪|H|). □

Proof for Theorem 3

For the first part, suppose − is a model-based contraction function for K with a determining pre-order ≼. Define ≼ H as follows:

  1. 1.

    If μ, ν∉|K|∖|H|, then μ H ν iff μν,

  2. 2.

    If μ, ν ∈ |K|∖|H|, then μ H ν, μ H ω 1, and ω 2 H μ for all ω 1∉|K| and ω 2∈|H|.

Clearly ≼ H is a faithful pre-order for H. Let \(\dot {-}\) be a MHC for H that is determined by ≼ H . It remains to show \(H\dot {-}\phi =\mathcal {H}(K-\phi )\) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\).

⊇: Suppose \(\psi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\) and ψKϕ. We need to show \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \). Since ψKϕ, we have by \((K\dot {-} 2)\) that ψK. Since H contains all the Horn formulas of K, we have ψH. If ϕK, then since H is a subset of K we have ϕH which implies by \((H\dot {-} 3)\) that \(H=H\dot {-}\phi \). Thus \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \) for the case of ϕK. Now suppose ϕK. Then we have |¬ϕ|∩|K| = . Since ψKϕ, we have by the construction of model-based contraction that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆|ψ|. By the definition of ≼ H (part 1), we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H ) = m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼). Thus m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H )⊆|ψ|. Since ψH implies |H|⊆|ψ|, we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H )∪|H|⊆|ψ| which implies C l (m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H )∪|H|)⊆|ψ|. Finally, it follows from the construction of MHC, \(|H\dot {-}\phi |\subseteq |\psi |\).

⊆: Suppose \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \). We need to show ψKϕ. Since \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \) we have by \((H\dot {-} 2)\) that ψH. Since H is a subset of K, we have ψK. If ϕH, then since H contains all the Horn formulas of K, we have ψK which implies by \((K\dot {-} 3)\) that K = Kϕ. Thus ψKϕ for the case of ϕH. Now suppose ϕH. Then ϕK which implies |¬ϕ|∩|K| = . Since \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \), we have by the construction of MHC, C l (m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H )∪|H|)⊆|ψ| which implies m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H )⊆|ψ|. By the definition of ≼ H (part 1), we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼ H ) = m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼). Thus m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆|ψ|. Since ψK implies |K|⊆|ψ|, we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∪⊆|ψ| which implies by the construction of model-based contraction that |Kϕ|⊆|ψ|.

The second part can be proved in a similar manner. This time we need to generate a pre-order for K from the one for H. □

Proof for Theorem 4

It suffices to show (1) if \(\dot {-}\) is a MHC function for H, then there is a TRPMHC function − for H such that \(H\dot {-}\phi =H-\phi \) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\) and (2) if \(\dot {-}\) is a TRPMHC function for H, then there is a MHC function − for H such that \(H\dot {-}\phi =H-\phi \) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\).

For the first part, suppose \(\dot {-}\) is a MHC function for H and is determined by the pre-order ≼. We first derive a relation ≤ over all weak remainder sets of H as follows:

For each pair X, Y of weak remainder sets of H, let YX iff X, Y are such that |X| = C l (|H| ∪ {μ}), |Y| = C l (|H| ∪ {ν}), and μν.

Now we show ≤ is transitive. Suppose X, Y, Z are weak remainder sets of H, XY and YZ, it suffices to show XZ. By the derivation of ≤, there are interpretations μ, ν, and ω such that |X| = C l (|H| ∪ {μ}), |Y| = C l (|H| ∪ {ν}), and |Z| = C l (|H| ∪ {ω}). Moreover, it follows from XY that νμ and it follows from YZ that ων. Since ≼ is transitive, it follows from νμ and ων that ωμ. Again by derivation of ≤, it follows from ωμ, that XZ.

Since ≤ is a transitive relation over all weak remainder sets of H, it can generate a TRPMHC function for H. Suppose the generated function is −, it remains to show \(H\dot {-}\phi =H-\phi \) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{H}\). If ϕH or ⊩ϕ, then we can easily obtain \(H\dot {-}\phi =H-\phi =H\). So suppose ϕH and ⊯ϕ. Let m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼) = {μ 1,…,μ n }. Then we have by the definition of MHC that \(H\dot {-}\phi =\mathcal {T}_{H}(|H|\cup \{\mu _{1},\ldots ,\mu _{n}\})\). By the definition of weak remainder set, there are X 1,…,X n H w ϕ such that |X i | = C l (|H| ∪ {μ i }) for 1≤in. Since m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼) = {μ 1,…,μ n }, we have, by the derivation of ≤ that {XH w ϕ | YX for all YH w ϕ} = {X 1,…,X n }. Then we have by the definition of TRPMHC that \(H-\phi =X_{1}\cap \cdots \cap X_{n}=\mathcal {T}_{H}(|X_{1}\cap \cdots \cap X_{n}|)= \mathcal {T}_{H}(Cl_{\cap }(|H|\cup \{\mu _{1}\}\cup \cdots \cup |H|\cup \{\mu _{n}\}))= \mathcal {T}_{H}(Cl_{\cap }(\{\mu _{1},\ldots ,\mu _{n}\}\cup |H|))= H\dot {-}\phi \).

The second part can be proved in a similar manner. This time we need to derive a pre-order over Ω for H from a transitive relation over all weak remainder sets of H. □

Proof for Theorem 5

Let \(\dot {-}\) be a SHCMHC function for H. We need to show there is a EHC function − for H such that \(H\dot {-}\phi =H-\phi \) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\).

Let ≼ be a pre-order. We use m i n(|ϕ|, ≼)≼m i n(|ψ|, ≼) to denote that for all μm i n(|ψ|, ≼) there is νm i n(|ϕ|, ≼) such that νμ and m i n(|ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|ψ|, ≼) to denote that for all μm i n(|ψ|, ≼) there is νm i n(|ϕ|, ≼) such that νμ.

We first show that if a MHC function \(\dot {-}\) for H is determined by the pre-order ≼, then \(\dot {-}\) satisfies the following condition:

$$\psi\in H\dot{-}\phi iff \psi\in H~\text{and either} \vdash\phi~\text{or}~min(|\neg\phi|,\preceq)\prec min(|\neg\phi\wedge\neg\psi|,\preceq). $$

For one direction, suppose \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \) and ⊯ϕ. We need to show ψH and m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼). Since \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \), ψH follows from \((H\dot {-} 2)\). It remains to show m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼). If |¬ϕ∧¬ψ| = , then the result holds trivially. So suppose |¬ϕ∧¬ψ|≠. By the definition of MHC, \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \) implies C l (|H| ∪ m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼))⊆|ψ|. Thus m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∩|¬ψ| = . Let μm i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼). Then we have for all νm i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼), νμ for otherwise m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∩|¬ψ|≠. Thus m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼).

For the other direction, suppose ψH, m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼), and ⊯ϕ. We need to show \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \). Since ψH, we have |H|⊆|ψ|. Since m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼), we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)∩|¬ψ| = which implies m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)⊆|ψ|. Thus C l (|H| ∪ m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼))⊆|ψ| which implies by the definition of MHC that \(\psi \in H\dot {-} \phi \).

Now we show that if ≼ is strict Horn compliant, then m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼) iff there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\) such that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬χ|, ≼).

For one direction, suppose m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼). We have to show there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\) such that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬χ|, ≼). If ϕψ is a Horn formula, then its only Horn strengthening is itself thus the result holds trivially. So suppose ϕψ is non-Horn. Then there exist two largest (by set inclusion) model sets X, Y⊆|ϕψ| such that XY = , for each xX there is yY such that xy = w and w ∈ |¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, and for each yY there is xX such that xy = w and w ∈ |¬ϕ∧¬ψ|. Since ≼ is strict Horn compliant, for each pair of x and y we have either wx or wy. Assume, without loss of generality, that wy for all such pairs. Let |χ| = |ϕψ|∖Y then, by the definition of Horn strengthening, we have \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\). Since |¬χ| = |¬ϕ∧¬ψ| ∪ Y, then by the derivation of χ we have m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼)≼m i n(|¬χ|, ≼). Then by the transitivity of ≼ we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬χ|, ≼).

For the other direction, suppose there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\) such that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬χ|, ≼). We have to show m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼). Since |χ|⊆|ϕψ| we have |¬ϕ∧¬ψ|⊆|¬χ| which implies m i n(|¬χ|, ≼)≼m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼). Then by the transitivity of ≼ we have m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬ϕ∧¬ψ|, ≼).

It follows from the above results that if \(\dot {-}\) is a SHCMHC function for H that is determined by the pre-order ≼, then it satisfies the following condition:

\((SHC\dot {-})\): \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \) iff ψH and either ⊩ϕ or there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\) such that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬χ|, ≼).

Now we derive a relation ≤ over \(\mathcal {L}\) from the pre-order ≼ as follows:

For \(\phi ,\psi \in \mathcal {L}\), ϕψ iff m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≼m i n(|¬ψ|, ≼)

It has been shown that the relation ≤ derived from ≼ as above is an epistemic entrenchment [26]. Thus ≤ can be used to determine an EHC function via \((HC\dot {-})\). Let − be the EHC function for H that is determined by ≤. It remains to show \( H\dot {-}\phi =H-\phi \) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\).

For one direction, suppose \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \). We need to show ψHϕ. By \((SHC\dot {-})\), \(\psi \in H\dot {-}\phi \) implies ψH and either ⊩ϕ or there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi \vee \psi )\) such that m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼)≺m i n(|¬χ|, ≼). By the derivation of ≤, the last part implies ϕ<χ. Thus it follows from \((HC\dot {-})\) that ψHϕ. The other direction can be proved in a similar manner. □

Proof for Theorem 6

Suppose |H|∩|ϕ|≠. By the construction of SHCIR, \(|H*\phi |=Cl_{\cap }(|H\dot {-}\chi _{1}|\cup \cdots \cup |H\dot {-}\chi _{n}|)\cap |\phi |\) where \(\dot {-}\) is the SHCMHC function that generates ∗ and \(\mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )=\{\chi _{1},\ldots ,\chi _{n}\}\). By the definition of Horn strengthenings we have |χ i |⊆|¬ϕ| which implies |ϕ|⊆|¬χ i | for 1≤in. Thus |H|∩|¬χ i |≠ which implies Hχ i . It then follows from \((H\dot {-} 3)\) that \(H\dot {-}\chi _{i}=H\). Thus |Hϕ| = |H|∩|ϕ|. Then by the faithfulness of ≼, |H|∩|ϕ| = m i n(|ϕ|, ≼).

Now suppose |H|∩|ϕ| = . For one direction, suppose μ ∈ |Hϕ|. We need to show μm i n(|ϕ|, ≼). By the definition of SHCIR, |Hϕ| = C l (C l (Hm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼))∪⋯∪C l (Hm i n(|¬χ n |,≼)))∩|ϕ|. Since μ ∈ |Hϕ|, by Lemma 5 there is νC l (Hm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼))∪⋯∪C l (Hm i n(|¬χ n |,≼)) such that μν. Thus there is χ i such that νC l (Hm i n(|¬χ i |,≼)). Again, by Lemma 5, there is σHm i n(|¬χ i |,≼) such that νσ. By the faithfulness of ≼ we cannot have σ ∈ |H|, thus it must be that σm i n(|¬χ i |,≼). Since |ϕ|⊆|¬χ i |, σm i n(|¬χ i |,≼) implies σx for all x ∈ |ϕ|. By the transitivity of ≼, it follows from μν and νσ that μσ. Thus we have μx for all x ∈ |ϕ| which implies μm i n(|ϕ|, ≼).

For the other direction, suppose μm i n(|ϕ|, ≼). We need to show μ ∈ |Hϕ|. Assume to the contrary that μ∉|Hϕ|. Recall that |Hϕ| = C l (C l (Hm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼))∪⋯∪C l (Hm i n(|¬χ n |,≼)))∩|ϕ|. We first show that the assumption leads to |Hϕ|∩|ϕ| = .

Assume there is ω ∈ |ϕ| such that ω ∈ |Hϕ| which implies ωC l (C l (Hm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼))∪⋯∪C l (Hm i n(|¬χ n |,≼))). Again, by Lemma 5, there is σm i n(|¬χ i |,≼) such that ωσ for some \(\chi _{i}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\). Since μm i n(|ϕ|, ≼) and ω ∈ |ϕ|, we have μω. It then follows from ωσ and μω that μω which implies μ ∈ |ϕ|⊆|¬χ i |, a contradiction. Thus we have |Hϕ|∩|ϕ| = .

Now Let ωm i n(|¬χ i |,≼) for some \(\chi _{i}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\). Then there is \(\chi _{j}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\) such that ω∉|¬χ j | for otherwise it follows from Lemma 2 that ω ∈ |ϕ| which contradicts |Hϕ|∩|ϕ| = . Let νm i n(|¬χ j |,≼). Since ω ∈ |χ j |, ν∉|χ j |, and ν ∈ |¬ϕ|, we have by the definition of Horn strengthening that ων ∈ |ϕ|. Since ω, νC l (C l (Hm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼))∪⋯∪C l (Hm i n(|¬χ n |,≼))), we have ωνC l (C l (Hm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼))∪⋯∪C l (Hm i n(|¬χ n |,≼))) which implies |Hϕ|∩|ϕ|≠, a contradiction. □

Proof for Theorem 8

Let \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\) be such that \(\mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )=\{\chi _{1},\ldots ,\chi _{n}\}\). By Lemma 2 we have |¬ϕ| = |χ 1|∪⋯∪|χ n | which implies, by De Morgan’s laws, |ϕ| = |¬χ 1|∩⋯∩|¬χ n |. Assume to the contrary that m i n(|¬χ|, ≼)∩|ϕ| = for all \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\). Let μm i n(|¬χ i |,≼) for some \(\chi _{i}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\), then there is \(\chi _{j}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\) such that μ∉|¬χ j | for otherwise it follows from |ϕ| = |¬χ 1|∩⋯∩|¬χ n | that μ ∈ |ϕ| which contradicts the fact that m i n(|¬χ|, ≼)∩|ϕ| = for all \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\). Let νm i n(|¬χ j |,≼). Since μ ∈ |χ j |, ν∉|χ j | and ν ∈ |¬ϕ|, we have by the definition of Horn strengthening that μν ∈ |ϕ|. It then follows from |ϕ| = |¬χ 1|∩⋯∩|¬χ n |, that μν ∈ |¬χ i | and μν ∈ |¬χ j |. Due to the strict Horn compliance of ≼, we have either μνμ or μνν which implies either μνm i n(|¬χ i ,≼)| or μνm i n(|¬χ j ,≼)|, a contradiction. Thus there is \(\chi \in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\) such that m i n(|¬χ|, ≼)∩|ϕ|≠.

Let’s assume, without loss of generality, that \(\chi _{1}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )\) is such that m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)∩|ϕ|≠. By Theorem 6 we have |Hϕ| = m i n(|ϕ|, ≼). Thus it suffices to show \(|H\dot {-}\chi _{1}+\phi | = min(|\phi |,\preceq )\). For one direction, we have, by the construction of MHC and IR, that \(|H\dot {-}\chi _{1}+\phi |=Cl_{\cap } (|H|\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ))\cap |\phi | \subseteq Cl_{\cap }(Cl_{\cap }(H\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ))\cup \cdots \cup Cl_{\cap }(H\cup min(|\neg \chi _{n}|,\preceq )))\cap |\phi |=|H*\phi |= min(|\phi |,\preceq )\). For the other direction, suppose μm i n(|ϕ|, ≼). Let νm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)∩|ϕ|. Then we have μν. Since |ϕ|⊆|¬χ 1|, we have μ ∈ |¬χ 1|. Thus it follows from νm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼) and μν that μm i n(|¬χ 1|,≼). Thus m i n(|ϕ|, ≼)⊆m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)∩|ϕ|⊆C l (|H| ∪ m i n χ 1|)∩|ϕ| = |Hχ 1 + ϕ|. □

Proof Proof for Lemma 6

Suppose μ, ν ∈ |ϕ| and μν. Since \(\mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )=\{\chi _{1},\chi _{2},\ldots ,\chi _{n}\}\), we have by the definition of Horn strengthenings that |χ i |⊆|¬ϕ| which implies |ϕ|⊆|¬χ i | for 1≤in. We first show \(\mu \preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}} \nu \). There are three cases:

  • Case 1,  μ, νC l (|H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)): \(\mu \preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}} \nu \) follows immediately from HC2.

  • Case 2,  μC l (|H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)): It follows from HC1 that μ is minimal in \(\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}}\). Thus \(\mu \preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}}\nu \).

  • Case 3,  νC l (|H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)) and μC l (|H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼)): If ν ∈ |H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼), then μν implies μ ∈ |H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼), a contradiction. If ν∉|H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼), then by Lemma 5, there is δ ∈ |H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼) such that νδ. It then follows from μν and the transitivity of ≼ that μδ which implies μ ∈ |H| ∪ m i n(|¬χ 1|,≼), a contradiction.

\(\mu \preceq ^{-_{i}}_{\chi _{i}}\nu \) for 2≤in can be proved inductively in the same manner as for \(\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}}\). The proof for the opposite direction is similar. □

Proof for Theorem 9

Suppose \(\mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi )=\{\chi _{1},\chi _{2},\ldots ,\chi _{n}\}\). Then by the definition of Horn strengthenings we have |χ i |⊆|¬ϕ| which implies |ϕ|⊆|¬χ i | for 1≤in. It follows from the definition of SHCSR that \(|H*\phi |= |((\cdots ((H-_{1}\chi _{1})-_{2}\chi _{2})\cdots )-_{n}\chi _{n})+\phi |= Cl_{\cap }(|H|\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ) \cup min(|\neg \chi _{2}|,\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}})\cup \cdots \cup min(|\neg \chi _{n}|,\preceq ^{-_{n-1}}_{\chi _{n-1}}))\cap |\phi |\) where −1 is the SHCMHC function that generates ∗. Note that HC1 and HC2 are used for deriving all the posterior pre-orders \(\preceq _{\chi _{1}}^{-_{1}},\ldots ,\preceq _{\chi _{n-1}}^{-_{n-1}}\) which in turn determine the MHC functions −2,…,− n . Let \(\preceq ^{-_{0}}_{\chi _{0}}=\preceq \).

For one direction, suppose ω ∈ |Hϕ|, we need to show ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼) There are three cases:

  • Case 1,  ω ∈ |H|: It follows from the faithfulness of ≼ that ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼).

  • Case 1,  there is χ i such that \(\omega \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\): Since ω ∈ |ϕ|⊆|¬χ i |, \(\omega \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\) implies \(\omega \in min(|\phi |,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\). Since \(min(|\phi |,\preceq )=min(|\phi |,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i}-1})\) follows from Lemma 6, we have ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼).

  • Case 1,  ω is induced by models in \(|H|\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ) \cup min(|\neg \chi _{2}|,\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}})\cup \cdots \cup min(|\neg \chi _{n}|,\preceq ^{-_{n-1}}_{\chi _{n-1}})\) : Since ≼ satisfies SHC, it follows from Lemma 5 that there is \(\mu \in |H|\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ) \cup min(|\neg \chi _{2}|,\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}})\cup \cdots \cup min(|\neg \chi _{n}|,\preceq ^{-_{n-1}}_{\chi _{n-1}})\) such that ωμ. If μ ∈ |H|, then it follows from ω∉|H| and the faithfulness of ≼ that μω which contradicts ωμ. So there is χ i such that \(\mu \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\). Due to HC1 and HC2, the rankings for models of ϕ are not downgraded throughout the contraction sequence. It then follows from ω ∈ |ϕ| and ωμ that \(\omega \preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}} \mu \). Thus \(\omega \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\) which implies, as in Case 2, ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼).

For the other direction, suppose ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼), we need to show ω ∈ |Hϕ|. Assume ω∉|Hϕ|. We first show that the assumption implies |Hϕ|∩|ϕ| = . Assume there is μ ∈ |ϕ| such that μ ∈ |Hϕ|. There are three cases.

  • Case 1,  μ ∈ |H|: It follows from the faithfulness of ≼ and ωμ that ω ∈ |H|, a contradiction.

  • Case 2,  there is χ i such that \(\mu \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\): It follows from Lemma 6 and ωμ that \(\omega \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\), a contradiction.

  • Case 3,  μ is induced by models in \(|H|\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ) \cup min(|\neg \chi _{2}|,\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}})\cup \cdots \cup min(|\neg \chi _{n}|,\preceq ^{-_{n-1}}_{\chi _{n-1}})\) : Since ≼ satisfies SHC, it follows from Lemma 5 that there is \(\nu \in |H|\cup min(|\neg \chi _{1}|,\preceq ) \cup min(|\neg \chi _{2}|,\preceq ^{-_{1}}_{\chi _{1}})\cup \cdots \cup min(|\neg \chi _{n}|,\preceq ^{-_{n-1}}_{\chi _{n-1}})\) such that μν. It then follows from ωμ and the transitivity of ≼ that ων. Then, with the same reasoning as in the Case 3 above, we can derive a contradiction.

Since all cases lead to a contradiction, we have |Hϕ|∩|ϕ| = . Let \(\mu \in min(|\neg \chi _{i}|,\preceq ^{-_{i-1}}_{\chi _{i-1}})\) . Then there is χ j such that μ∉|¬χ j | for otherwise μ ∈ |ϕ| which leads to |Hϕ|∩|ϕ|≠. Let \(\nu \in min(|\neg \chi _{j}|,\preceq ^{-_{j-1}}_{\chi _{j-1}})\). Since μ ∈ |χ j |, ν∉|χ j |, and ν ∈ |¬ϕ|, we have by the definition of Horn strengthening that μν ∈ |ϕ|. Since μ, ν ∈ |Hϕ| = C l (|Hϕ|), we have μν ∈ |Hϕ| which implies |Hϕ|∩|ϕ|≠, a contradiction. □

Proof Proof for Lemma 7

For one direction suppose ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼), we need to show ωm i n(|χ 1|,≼)∪⋯∪m i n(|χ n |,≼). By Lemma 2 there is \(\chi _{i}\in \mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi )\) such that ω ∈ |χ i |. By the definition of Horn strengthening, |χ|⊆|ϕ| for all Horn strengthenings χ of ϕ. Thus there is no χ such that μ ∈ |χ| and μω which implies \(\chi _{i}\in min(\mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\phi ),\preceq )\) and we are done.

For the other direction, suppose ωm i n(|χ 1|,≼)∪⋯∪m i n(|χ n |,≼), we need to show ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼). Without loss of generality, let ωm i n(|χ 1|,≼). Since |χ 1|⊆|ϕ|, we have ω ∈ |ϕ|. By the first part of the proof, we have m i n(|χ|, ≼)⊆m i n(|χ 1|,≼)∪⋯∪m i n(|χ n |,≼). Thus it follows from the definition of most preferred formulas and ωm i n(|χ 1|,≼) that μω for all μm i n(|χ|, ≼) which implies ωm i n(|ϕ|, ≼). □

Proof for Theorem 11

For one direction, suppose \(\dot {-}\) is a MHC function for H that is determined by the pre-order ≼, we need to show \(\dot {-}\) is an IC function for H. Suppose ∗ is the MHR function for H that is determined by ≼. Let − be the IC function generated by ∗. It suffices to show \(|H\dot {-}\phi |=|H-\phi |\) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\). Let \(min(\mathcal {H}\mathcal {S}(\neg \phi ),\preceq )=\{\chi _{1},\ldots ,\chi _{n}\}\). By the definition of MHC and IC functions, we have \(|H\dot {-}\phi |=Cl_{\cap }(|H|\cup min(|\neg \phi |,\preceq ))\) and |Hϕ| = C l (|H| ∪ m i n(|χ 1|,≼),…,m i n(|χ n |,≼)). Thus it suffices to show |H| ∪ m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼) = |H| ∪ m i n(|χ 1|,≼),…,m i n(|χ n |,≼) which follows immediately from Lemma 7.

For the other direction, suppose \(\dot {-}\) is an IC function for H that is generated from the MHR function ∗ for H, we need to show \(\dot {-}\) is a MHC function for H. Suppose the determining pre-order for ∗ is ≼. Now suppose − is a MHC function for H that is determined by ≼. It suffices to show \(|H\dot {-}\phi |=|H-\phi |\) for all \(\phi \in \mathcal {L}_{\text {\texttt {H}}}\). As in the first part of the proof, this comes down to showing |H| ∪ m i n(|¬ϕ|, ≼) = |H| ∪ m i n(|χ 1|,≼),…,m i n(|χ n |,≼) which follows immediately from Lemma 7. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zhuang, Z., Pagnucco, M. & Zhang, Y. Inter-Definability of Horn Contraction and Horn Revision. J Philos Logic 46, 299–332 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-016-9401-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-016-9401-2

Keywords

Navigation