Skip to main content
Log in

The Burdens of Love

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

While we primarily love individual persons, we also love our work, our homes, our activities and causes. To love is to be engaged in an active concern for the objective well-being—the thriving—of whom and what we love. True love mandates discovering in what that well-being consists and to be engaged in the details of promoting it. Since our loves are diverse, we are often conflicted about the priorities among the obligations they bring. Loving requires constant contextual improvisatory adjustment of priorities among our commitments. Besides delighting in—and being enhanced by—the presence and existence of another person (a place, an institution, profession), love requires extended reflection and work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In isolating love as a subject for philosophical analysis, we abstract it from its phenomenological complexities and its psychological contexts. (See Sects. 3 and 4). See (of all people) Hume, Treatise Of the Human Understanding 2.2.9 SB 384-5. “Tis not the present sensation …which determines the character of any passion, but the general bent and tendency of it from beginning to end.”

  2. See the essays by Geertz et al. (1984), Rosaldo (1986).

  3. See, for example, Strachey (1959), Freud (1947), Bowlby (1969/1999).

  4. See, e.g., Kraut (1986), Rorty (1986a), Badhwar (2003). Kolodny (2003), Velleman (1999), Setiya (2014), Jollimore (2011).

  5. See Kant (1963); Emerson (1841).

  6. See Stocker (1976, 1979).

  7. I am grateful to MindaRae Amiran and Richard Schmitt for stressing this point.

  8. Although personal love by no means exhausts the range of our loves, I shall, for the sake of simplicity, initially use the example of romantic love to examine the structure and dynamics of generic love. In Sect. 4, I will turn to other, familiar but less often analyzed expressions of love—the love of home, of a profession or of an activity.

  9. Plato himself has Socrates describe the Divided Line without introducing the political analysis that forms the bulk of the rest of the work. (Republic VI, 509D-513E.) I’ll return to the connection between love and political activism in Sect. 4.

  10. See Rorty (1986b).

  11. The distinction between the causes and constituents of love presupposes a full dress analysis of the content, structure and dynamics of intentional attitudes that I cannot undertake here. See e.g. Anscombe (1957), Thalberg (1993), Aquila (1975).

  12. I am grateful to Bill Ruddick for this example and to Berislav Marusic for objecting that love of causes and country, activities and professions do not carry the same kind of care and concern of personal love. It is true, Arthur does not move to Venice or undertake to become a professional art conservationist. But his love does not just consist in a passing elation during a visit to Venice. For it to be an authentic love rather than generalized elation, it must be expressed, (as it might be) by his contributing to the Save Venice Fund and organizing a campaign to prevent the Scuola di san Rocco from selling “The Raising of Lazarus” to Donald Trump for his private collection. Less dramatically and more subtly, Arthur’s love of Tintoretto would be expressed by changes in his perceptual range, by his increased sensitivity to the dramas of light and shadows, by his doing some research on Tintoretto’s palette and studio.

  13. Because I do not understand them, I have omitted two significant directions of love: the love of God (and God’s love of Mankind) described by Augustine (1950, 2002) and the love of Humanity described by Kant (1996). Augustine thinks the ability to recognize and fulfill the obligation to love God is itself a gift of grace; Kant believes that fulfilling the duties of the love of Humanity falls to the rational will.

  14. I am grateful to Avner Baz for pointing out that “a commitment to [one’s] job is a part of a commitment to [oneself], while a commitment to one's partner is a commitment to her/him.” It’s true that Abe’s commitment to Ella is focused on her, rather than on himself as a media consultant, still his commitment to Ella is an essential part of his self-understanding, to himself-as-loving-Ella.

  15. I am grateful to Richard Schmitt for stressing this point. See Rorty, “The Historicity of Love…” loc. cit. and Benjamin Bagley (2015).

  16. See Held (2006), Haslanger (2012) and Rorty (1998).

  17. I am grateful to Richard Schmitt and to Robert Frederick for raising this concern.

  18. I am grateful to MindaRae Amiran, Avner Baz, Robert Frederick, Berislav Marusic, Richard Schmitt and Ben Sherman for comments.

References

  • Anscombe, Elizabeth. 1957. Intention. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. 1950. The City of God XIV.7. trans. Marcus Dods, 448–449. New York: Random House.

  • Augustine. 2002. On the Trinity IX. 2–5, 8, ed. Gareth Matthews, trans. Stephen McKenna, 25–31, 34–35. Cambridge University Press.

  • Aquila, Richard E. 1975. Causes and constituents of occurent emotions. The Philosophical Quarterly 25: 346–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Badhwar, Neera. 2003. Love. In Practical ethics, ed. H. LaFollette, 42–69. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagley, Benjamin. 2015. Loving someone in particular. Ethics 125(2): 477–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowlby, John. 1969/1999. Attachment and loss (vol. 1) (2nd ed.). New York: Basic Books.

  • Butler, Joseph. Sermon IX.

  • Emerson, Ralph Waldo. 1841. Love. Essays: First Series.

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 2001. The dear self. Philosophers Imprint 1(5): 55–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1947. Contributions to the psychology of love. Freud on war, sex and neurosis, 231. New York: Arts and Science Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, Clifford, Richard Shweder and Robert Levy. 1984. From the native's point of view. In Culture theory, ed. Richard Shweder and Robert LeVine, 123–136. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, Sally. 2012. Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Held, Virginia. 2006. The ethics of care: Personal, political, and global. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. Treatise of the human understanding 2.2.9 SB 384-5.

  • Jollimore, Troy. 2011. Love’s vision. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant. 1963. Friendship. In Lectures on Ethics, ed. Louis Beck, trans. Louis Infield, 200-209. New York: Harper and Row.

  • Kant. 1996. Metaphysics of morals, II, 1.1. 25–30. trans. Mary Gregor, (6:449–6:452) 199–201. Cambridge University Press.

  • Kolodny, Nico. 2003. Love as valuing a relationship. The Philosophical Review 11: 135–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, Robert. 1986. Love De Re. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10: 413–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Amelie. 1986a. The historicity of love: Love is not love when it alters not when it alteration finds. Midwest Studies in the Philosophy of Mind 10: 121–134. (reprinted in Mind in Action Boston: Beacon Press, 1988/1991 121–135).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Amelie. (1986b). The historicity of psychological attitudes: Love is not love which alters not when it alteration finds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10: 399–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Amelie. 1998. On being rational. Ratio 22: 350–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosaldo, Renato. 1986. From the door to his tent. In Writing culture, ed. James Clifford, and George Marcus. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, Kieran. 2014. Love and the value of a life. The Philosophical Review 123: 251–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, Michael. 1976. The schizophrenia of modern ethical theories. The Journal of Philosophy 73: 453–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, Michael. 1979. On desiring the bad: An essay in moral psychology. The Journal of Philosophy 86: 46–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strachey, James. ed. & trans. 1959. Group psychology and the analysis of the ego. New York: Norton.

  • Thalberg, Irving. 1993. Constituents and causes of emotion and action. The Philosophical Quarterly 23: 137–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, David. 1999. Love as a moral emotion. Ethics 109(2): 338–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amelie Rorty.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rorty, A. The Burdens of Love. J Ethics 20, 341–354 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-016-9216-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-016-9216-y

Keywords

Navigation