Skip to main content
Log in

Re-enchanting Realism in Debate with Kyle Stanford

  • Discussion
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, against the background of a notion of ‘assembled’ truth, the evolutionary progressiveness of a theory is suggested as novel and promising explanation for the success of science. A new version of realism in science, referred to as ‘naturalised realism’ is outlined. Naturalised realism is ‘fallibilist’ in the unique sense that it captures and mimics the self-corrective core of scientific knowledge and its progress. It is argued that naturalised realism disarms Kyle Stanford’s anti-realist ‘new induction’ threats by showing that ‘explanationism’ and his ‘epistemic instrumentalism’ are just two positions among many on a constantly evolving continuum of options between instrumentalism and full-blown realism. In particular it is demonstrated that not only can naturalised realism redefine the terms of realist debate in such a way that no talk of miracles need enter the debate, but it also promises interesting defenses against inductive- and under-determination-based anti-realist arguments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. This idea is also found in belief revision of the AGM kind (e.g. Alchourron et al. 1985; Gärdenfors 1990), and perhaps even in some versions of semantic information theory (Shannon 1948; Carnap and Bar-Hillel 1952).

  2. This history is actually a history of theoretical-empirical interactions that have mutual impact on each other, but in what follows the focus is on how changes at the empirical level impact on the theoretical level.

  3. See also Putnam (1981) to understand the sentiments driving the naturalised realist’s non-representational notion of truth-as-reference.

  4. And so, perhaps all that can be said of truth is that it is sincere and accurate (viz. Williams 2002).

  5. ‘Assemblance’ meaning ‘the state of being gathered or collected’.

  6. Magnus (2006) offers an argument, based on aspects of the change from classical to relativistic mechanics, which concludes that instances of both transient under-determination and new induction are much more common place and perhaps natural in science than Stanford, at least on the face of it, seems to allow for—or is able to allow for, given his explanationist target.

  7. Think again of AGM belief revision.

  8. There is a lively debate on this issue which cannot be covered here—see for instance Laudan (1984), Ladyman and Ross (2007), Doppelt (2002), Chang (2003), Lyons (2006), Votsis (2005) and many others.

  9. The naturalised realist’s full account of reference cannot be unpacked here, but briefly, the argument is that the open-endedness of science in the context of referential continuity makes more sense if the emphasis is on the causal role an entity plays in virtue of an empirically adapted core causal description associated with the term denoting the entity.

References

  • Alchourron, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction functions and their associated revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1990). Realism, conventionality, and ‘realism about’. In G. Boolos (Ed.) Meaning and method: Essays in honour of Hilary Putnam. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Burch, R. (2010). Charles Sanders Peirce. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/peirce/.

  • Carnap, R., & Bar-Hillel, Y. (1952). An outline of a theory of semantic information. Cambridge MA: Research Laboratory of Electronics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2003). Preservative realism and its discontents: Revisiting caloric. Philosophy of Science, 70, 902–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1991). Realism and truth. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2011). Are unconceived alternatives a problem for scientific realism? Journal of General Philosophy of Science. Published online: 30 August, 2011.

  • Doppelt, G. (2002). Book reviews: Relativism and reality: A contemporary introduction. By Robert Kirk. Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. By Stathis Psillos. The Philosophical Review, 111(1), 142–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doppelt, G. (2007). The value ladenness of scientific knowledge. In H. Kinciad, et al. (Eds.), Value-free science? Oxford scholarship online monographs. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T., & Rysiew, P. (2009). Fallibilism, epistemic possibility, and concessive knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXVIII(1), 123–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (1981). Fallibilism and knowing that one knows. The Philosophical Review, 90(2), 266–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1990). The dynamic of belief systems: Foundations vs coherence theories. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 172, 24–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2008). What’s wrong with contextualism? The Philosophical Quarterly, 58(232), 416–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1981). Lakatos’s philosophy of science. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolution (pp. 128–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hallum, A. (1973). A revolution in the earth sciences. From continental drift to plate tectonics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C., & Rosenberg, A. (1982). In defence of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 49, 604–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2005). Fallibilism. The Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (October 2005). http://www.iep.utm.edu/fallibil/.

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1978). Theories, theorists and theoretical change. Philosophical Review, 87, 519–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1982). Genes. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33(4), 337–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2000). The contextualist evasion of epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 10, 24–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2011). Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: The case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese, 180, 87–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). The methodology of scientific research programmes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Larvor, B. (1998). Lakatos. An introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Explaining the success of science: Beyond epistemic realism and relativism. In J. Cushing, et al. (Eds.), Science and reality (pp. 83–105). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (2004). A theory’s predictive Success can warrant belief in the unobservable entities it postulates. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 117–132). Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. D. (2006). Scientific realism and the Strategema de Divide et Impera. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 537–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2006). What’s new about the new induction? Synthese, 148(2), 295–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (Ed.). (1983). A pocket popper. Oxford: Fontana Paperbacks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1994). Critical rationalism: A restatement and defence. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgment. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (1986). Likeness to truth. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1955). The scientific attitude and fallibilism. In J. Buchler (Ed.), Philosophical writings of Peirce (pp. 42–59). New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1981). The rationality of scientific revolutions. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolutions (pp. 80–106). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1983). Scientific method, the aim of science, truth and approximation to truth, realism. In D. Miller (Ed.), A pocket popper (pp. 133–142, 162–170, 181–198, 220–225). Oxford: Fontana Paperbacks.

  • Popper, K. R. (1989). Conjectures and refutations. The growth of scientific knowledge (5th Ed. Revised). London: Routledge.

  • Psillos, S. (1997). Kitcher on reference. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 11(3), 259–272.

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism. How science tracks truth. Boston: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language, and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, B. (2002). How to think about fallibilism. Philosophical Studies, 107, 142–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1980). Scepticism: A critical reappraisal. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruttkamp, E. B. (2011). Interactive realism. South African Journal of Philosophy, 30(1), 41–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs, 35(4), 477–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2011). Epistemic contextualism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/contextualism-epistemology/.

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). From contextualism to contrastivism. Philosophical Studies, 119(1–2), 73–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). Contextualist solutions to skepticism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96, 317–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. E. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27(379–423), 625–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2000). An antirealist explanation of the success of science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 266–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2003a). Pyrrhic victories for scientific realism. Journal of Philosophy, 100(11), 553–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2003b). No refuge for realism: Selective confirmation and the history of science. Philosophy of Science, 70, 913–925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp. Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2009a). Underdetermination of scientific theory. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2009b Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009b/entries/scientific-underdetermination/.

  • Stanford, K. (2009b). Scientific realism, atomic theory, and the catch-all hypothesis: Can we test fundamental theories against all serious alternatives? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2004). On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 119(1–2), 119–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1972). Human understanding: The collective use and evolution of concepts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vicedo, M. (2000). Experimentation in early genetics. The implications of the historical character of science for scientific realism. In R. Creath & J. Maienschein (Eds.), Biology and epistemology (pp. 215–243). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Votsis, I. (2005). The upward path to structural realism. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 1361–1372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, M. (2005). Must we know what we say? The Philosophical Review, 114(2), 227–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, E. T. (1951). History of the theories of aether and electricity (revised edition). London: Thomas Nelson and Sons, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (2002). Truth and truthfullness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. T. (1968). Static or mobile earth: The current scientific revolution. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 112(5), 309–320.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emma Ruttkamp-Bloem.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ruttkamp-Bloem, E. Re-enchanting Realism in Debate with Kyle Stanford. J Gen Philos Sci 44, 201–224 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9220-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9220-x

Keywords

Navigation