Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Local Food and International Ethics

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many advocate practices of ‘local food’ or ‘locavorism’ as a partial solution to the injustices and unsustainability of contemporary food systems. I think that there is much to be said in favor of local food movements, but these virtues are insufficient to immunize locavorism from criticism. In particular, three duties of international ethics—beneficence, repair and fairness—may provide reasons for constraining the developed world’s permissible pursuit of local food. A complete account of why (and how) the fulfillment of these duties constrains locavorism will require extensive empirical evidence about the relationship between agricultural demand-led industrialization, international trade (rules), and local food practices. In this paper I can only gesture at some of this evidence and, for that reason, my policy prescriptions are merely provisional. Instead, the upshot of this paper is that advocates of locavorism ought to be attentive to the empirical-dependence of the moral permissibility of their projects. As local food ‘scales up’—and comes to be embraced as a goal of political communities—these concerns should receive even greater attention.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a helpful taxonomy of local food practices and movements, see Werkheiser and Noll (2013).

  2. Of course, duties of international ethics are not the only source of constraints upon the permissible pursuit of local food. For example, my duty to provide for my child’s basic needs prohibits me from spending hundreds of dollars on locally grown vine-ripened heirloom tomatoes if doing so would leave me unable to purchase her school supplies.

  3. I leave aside questions about international egalitarianism, i.e. whether the existence of transnational inequalities (of wealth, income, etc.) is evidence of injustice. Even if international inequality is not unjust in itself, non-egalitarian international ethical duties may generate significant constraints on the permissible pursuit of local food.

  4. Of course, historical and ongoing relationships help to determine which parties one is most able to assist.

  5. On the economics of international trade, see Krugman et al (2012); Hoekman and Kostecki (2009).

  6. To be clear, ADLI is a transitional strategy. It makes it possible for developing societies to develop more diverse (and stable) economies.

  7. For some discussion of this point, and of what follows, see Wade (2004); Vos (2012).

  8. Note, though, that Kurjanska and Risse (2008, 48–9) admit that Fair Trade may sometimes be a sensible development strategy, and that we often cannot know when it will (or will not be) a sensible strategy.

  9. One way to resist the conclusions that I draw from Singer’s account of beneficence is to assert that at least some of the developed world’s local food practices produce goods that are morally comparable to the goods produced through ADLI. For example, consider the Detroit Black Community Food Security Network (DBCFSN) (http://detroitblackfoodsecurity.org/). The mission of this group is “to build self-reliance, food security and food justice in Detroit’s Black community by influencing public policy, engaging in urban agriculture, promoting healthy eating, encouraging co-operative buying, and directing youth towards careers in food-related fields.” In the context of the broader public’s abandonment of inner-city Detroit, and in the absence of healthy food options for the people of the city, the goods that the DBCFSN pursues seem to be of ‘comparable moral importance’ to the alleviation of $2/day poverty in other countries.

  10. I take these terms from Barry and Øverland (2012).

  11. Another worry is that agricultural subsidies may improve the conditions of the poorest members of food-importing societies, e.g. by making imported food cheaper. See e.g. Kurjanska and Risse (2008). However, even if some of the world's poor are made better off by the developed world's protectionism, there is good evidence that tariffs, subsidies, and other protectionist trade policies are bad for the global poor in the aggregate.

  12. If Pogge is right, then some forms of institutional unfairness can be described as (contributions to) harms. But there are two reasons why this possibility presents no problem for my views. First, if Pogge is correct, then the broader goal of this section has already been accomplished: One should acknowledge that there are stringent duties (of repair, and not fairness) whose discharge would curtail the developed world's pursuit of local food, even if one does not think that a duty of beneficence is stringent. Second, there may be other forms of unfairness beyond those that Pogge characterizes in terms of (contributions to) harms.

  13. For example, Øverland (2013) argues that Pogge’s claim that affluent societies contribute to global poverty can best be understood as the claim that the affluent exploit the global poor (and not that they harm the global poor). One way in which one may exploit another is to benefit from unfair (but non-harmful) terms of cooperation.

  14. On the 'equal benefit' test for fairness in trade, see James (2012).

  15. For further argument in favor of ‘better than fair’ terms of trade for developing societies see Stiglitz and Charlton (2006).

  16. For example, consider the efforts made by local communities within the states of Vermont and Maine to demand food sovereignty (http://vermontfoodsovereignty.net/; http://www.farmfoodfreedom.org/updates/maine-town-declares-food-sovereignty). Similar efforts have been made in some European countries (http://internationalviewpoint.org/spip.php?article1825; http://foodsovereigntynow.org.uk/).

  17. Here, I need not take a side on the issue of whether beneficence ever requires one to do more than her fair share. Even if it does, questions about the further stringency of beneficence remain unanswered.

  18. Consider the following passage from John Rawls’s Political Liberalism: “Individuals and associations cannot comprehend the ramifications of their particular actions viewed collectively, nor can they be expected to foresee future circumstances that shape and transform present tendencies” (Rawls 1993, 268). See also, Thomas Pogge, from Freedom from Poverty as Human Right: “[T]he effects of my economic decision intermingle with the effects of billions of decisions made by others, and it is impossible to try to disentangle, even ex post, the impact of my decision from this vast traffic by trying to figure out how things would have gone had I acted differently” (Pogge 2007, 17, emphasis in original).

References

  • Adelman, I. (1984). Beyond export-led growth. World Development, 12(9), 937–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, C., & Øverland, G. (2012). The feasible alternatives thesis: Kicking away the livelihoods of the global poor. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 11(1), 97–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berry, W. (2009). Bringing It to the Table: On Farming and Food. Berkeley, California: Counterpoint Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittman, M. (2008). Food matters: A guide to conscious eating with more than 75 recipes. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittman, M. (2011). Don’t end agricultural subsidies, fix them. The New York Times, March 2. http://query.nytimes.com/gst/fullpage.html?res=9A0CEFD8133EF931A35750C0A9679D8B63.

  • Campesina, V. (1996). Tlaxcala declaration of the Vía Campesina. Tlaxcala, Mexico. http://viacampesina.org/en/index.php/our-conferences-mainmenu-28/2-tlaxcala-1996-mainmenu-48/425-ii-international-conference-of-the-via-campesina-tlaxcala-mexico-april-18-21.

  • Campesina, V. (2001). Our world is not for sale, priority to people’s food sovereignty, WTO out of food and agriculture. http://viacampesina.org/en/index.php/actions-and-events-mainmenu-26/10-years-of-wto-is-enough-mainmenu-35/323-statement-network-qour-world-is-not-for-saleq-owinfs.

  • Caney, S. (2006). Cosmopolitan justice, responsibility, and global climate change. Leiden Journal of International Law, 18(04), 747–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castaldo, S., Perrini, F., Misani, N., & Tencati, A. (2009). The missing link between corporate social responsibility and consumer trust: The case of fair trade products. Journal of Business Ethics, 84(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cline, W. R. (2004). Trade policy and global poverty. Washington: Peterson Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., & Sabel, C. (2006). Extra rempublicam nulla justitia? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 34(2), 147–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dercon, S. (2009). Rural poverty: Old challenges in new contexts. The World Bank Research Observer, 24(1), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dethier, J. J., & Effenberger, A. (2012). Agriculture and development: A brief review of the literature. Economic Systems, 36(2), 175–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunmore, C. (2013). Farm subsidies still get top share of EU austerity budget. Reuters, February 8, U.S. edition. http://www.reuters.com/article/2013/02/08/eu-budget-agriculture-idUSL5N0B82UW20130208.

  • Engler, M. (2012). Hijacked organic, limited local, faulty fair trade: What’s a radical to eat? Dissent, 59(2), 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fairtrade International. (2013). Fairtrade International. http://www.fairtrade.net/.

  • Grebitus, C., Lusk, J. L., & Nayga, R. M, Jr. (2013). Effect of distance of transportation on willingness to pay for food. Ecological Economics, 88, 67–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halweil, B. (2004). Eat here: Reclaiming homegrown pleasures in a global supermarket. W. W: Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassoun, N. (2011). Free trade, poverty, and inequality. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 8(1), 5–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayashikawa, M. (2009). Trading Out of Poverty–How Aid for Trade Can Help. OECD Journal on Development 10 (2).

  • Hoekman, B. M., & Kostecki, M. (2009). The political economy of the World Trading System: The WTO and beyond. Oxford, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaffee, D., Kloppenburg, J. R., & Monroy, M. B. (2004). Bringing the ‘moral charge’ home: Fair Trade within the North and within the South. Rural Sociology, 69(2), 169–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, A. (2012). Fairness in practice: A social contract for a global economy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, B. F., & Mellor, J. W. (1961). The role of agriculture in economic development. The American Economic Review, 51(4), 566–593.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingsolver, B., Kingsolver, C., & Hopp, S. L. (2008). Animal, vegetable, miracle: A year of food life. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krugman, P. R., Obstfeld, M., & Melitz, M. J. (2012). International economics: Theory and policy. Boston: Pearson Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurjanska, M., & Risse, M. (2008). Fairness in trade II: Export subsidies and the fair trade movement. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 7(1), 29–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martínez-Torres, M. E., & Rosset, P. M. (2010). La Vía Campesina: The birth and evolution of a transnational social movement. Journal of Peasant Studies, 37(1), 149–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKibben, B. (2008). Deep economy: The wealth of communities and the durable future. New York: St. Martin’s Griffin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. W. (2004). Beneficence, duty and distance. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32(4), 357–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. W. (2010). Globalizing justice: The ethics of poverty and power. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, B. (2007). Food miles or poverty eradication? The moral duty to eat African strawberries at Christmas. Institute for Energy Studies and Oxford Climate Change Policy.

  • Narveson, J. (2003). We don’t owe them a thing! A tough-minded but soft-hearted view of aid to the faraway needy. The Monist, 86(3), 419–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nixon, R. (2013). Senate Passes Farm Bill; House Vote Is Less Sure. The New York Times, June 10, sec. U.S./Politics. http://www.nytimes.com/2013/06/11/us/politics/senate-passes-farm-bill-house-vote-is-less-sure.html.

  • Nyéléni Food Sovereignty Forum. (2007). Declaration of Nyéléni.

  • O’Neill, O. (2000). Bounds of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Øverland, G. (2013). Pogge on poverty: Contribution or Exploitation? Journal of Applied Philosophy, 30(4), 319–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patel, R. (2008). Stuffed and starved: The hidden battle for the world food system. Brooklyn: Melville House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patten, A. (2005). Should we stop thinking about poverty in terms of helping the poor? Ethics and International Affairs, 19(1), 19–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pauw, K., & Thurlow, J. (2011). Agricultural growth, poverty, and nutrition in Tanzania. Food Policy, 36(6), 795–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, G. R. (2013). Is eating locally a moral obligation? Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 26, 421–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pimbert, M. (2009). Towards food sovereignty: Reclaiming autonomous food systems. London: IIED.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2004). ‘Assisting’ the Global Poor. In D. K. Chatterjee (Ed.), The ethics of assistance (pp. 260–288). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2005). Severe poverty as a violation of negative duties. Ethics and International Affairs, 19(1), 55–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2007). Freedom from poverty as a human right: Who owes what to the very poor? USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2008). World poverty and human rights (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollan, M. (2007). The omnivore’s dilemma: A natural history of four meals. Farmington Hills: Large Print Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999a). The law of peoples. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999b). A theory of justice (Rev ed.). Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risse, M. (2005). Do we owe the global poor assistance or rectification? Ethics and International Affairs, 19(1), 9–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risse, M. (2012). On global justice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosset, P. M. (2006). Food is different: Why the WTO should get out of agriculture. London: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruben, R., Fort, R., & Zúñiga-Arias, G. (2009). Measuring the impact of fair trade on development. Development in Practice, 19(6), 777–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satz, D. (2005). What do we owe the global poor? Ethics and International Affairs, 19(1), 47–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, C., Barber, A. & Taylor G. (2006). Food miles-comparative energy/emissions performance of New Zealand’s agriculture industry. Lincoln University. Agribusiness and Economics Research Unit. http://researcharchive.lincoln.ac.nz/dspace/handle/10182/125.

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schanbacher, W. D. (2010). The politics of food: The global conflict between food security and food sovereignty. Santa Barbara: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shue, H. (1993). Subsistence emissions and luxury emissions. Law and Policy, 15(1), 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shue, H. (1999). Global environment and international inequality. International Affairs, 75(3), 531–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2002). One world: The ethics of globalization. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P., & Mason, J. (2007). The ethics of what we eat: Why our food choices matter. Emmaus, Pennsylvania: Rodale Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. E., & Charlton, A. (2006). Fair trade for all. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valkila, J., & Nygren, A. (2010). Impacts of Fair Trade certification on coffee farmers, cooperatives, and laborers in Nicaragua. Agriculture and Human Values, 27(3), 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vos, R. (Ed.). (2012). Who gains from Free Trade: Export-Led growth, inequality and poverty in latin America. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wade, R. H. (2004). Is globalization reducing poverty and inequality? World Development, 32(4), 567–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, K., & Fowler, P. (2002). Rigged rules and double standards. Oxford: Oxfam International.

  • Weber, C. L., & Matthews, H. S. (2008). Food-miles and the relative climate impacts of food choices in the United States. Environmental Science and Technology, 42(10), 3508–3513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werkheiser, I, & Noll, S. (2013). From Food justice to a tool of the status Quo: Three sub-movements within local food. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics online first.

  • World Bank. (2007). World Development Report 2008: Agriculture for Development. Washington: World Bank.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank the following persons for their assistance on this paper: Dan Hicks, Kristina Jeffers, Joan McGregor, Samantha Noll, William Schanbacher, Ian Werkheiser and the members of Oakland University's Philosophy Department.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark C. Navin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Navin, M.C. Local Food and International Ethics. J Agric Environ Ethics 27, 349–368 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-014-9492-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-014-9492-0

Keywords

Navigation