Skip to main content
Log in

The desirability of workfare in the presence of misreporting

  • Published:
International Tax and Public Finance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we demonstrate that in addition to its acknowledged screening role, workfare—namely, introducing work (or training) requirements for welfare eligibility in means-tested programs—also serves to mitigate income misreporting by welfare claimants. It achieves this goal by effectively increasing the marginal cost of earning extra income in the shadow economy for claimants who satisfy the work requirement. We show that when misreporting is sufficiently prevalent, supplementing a means-tested transfer system with work requirements is socially desirable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The OECD Employment Outlook 2009 suggests, however, shifting somewhat the focus and resources behind activation from the “work-first” approach which tended to dominate prior to the current global economic crisis to a “train-first” approach for those at high risk of long-term unemployment.

  2. The 1996 Act required a minimum of 20 hours of work (or work related activities, such as training) per week to be eligible for a welfare cash transfer. Compliance was assured by an extensive use of sanctions including benefit reductions (for further details see US DHHS 2002).

  3. Screening is difficult as poor individuals are often characterized by low earning ability and ill health—information that is hard to observe or verify (King 2004).

  4. Besley and Coate acknowledge, however, that in the least-developing countries where means-testing is administratively infeasible, workfare could be justified on welfarist grounds, serving as a single screening device. Our argument, in contrast, applies to welfare systems that do rely on means testing, as is the case in most countries of the world, including the vast majority of developing countries, but where, plausibly, means-testing is mired by some misreporting issues. We argue that a major role played by workfare, in addition to screening (emphasized by the existing literature), is in enhancing the screening-effectiveness of means-testing, by mitigating the extent of misreporting. Notably, in the optimal welfare system, workfare supplements, rather than fully substitutes, means-testing.

  5. Contrary to Besley and Coate (1995), we demonstrate that imposing workfare may be warranted on normative grounds even when the government invokes a welfarist objective. In a recent paper (Beaudrey et al. 2009) show that wage subsidies rendered to low-market performers will be part of the optimal tax-transfer program chosen by a welfarist government. This result is obtained in a different setting than the standard Mirleesian framework which Besley and Coate (1992, 1995) as well as our paper follow. It assumes that the government can observe work time (in addition to earned income). Under such a setting a wage subsidy may be interpreted as a form of workfare.

  6. See discussion in footnote 4.

  7. This assumption does not affect the qualitative nature of our results.

  8. Misreporting may take different forms. One plausible interpretation is that welfare claimants work in the shadow economy in addition to holding low-paying jobs in the legal sector (based on which they claim eligibility for welfare transfers).

  9. Formally, \(\overline {V} = \max_{y} [y-h(y/\overline {w})]\) and \(\underline {V} = \max_{y} [y-h(y/\underline {w})]\), with y denoting the level of income given by y=wl.

  10. The literature on the design of welfare systems usually distinguishes between universal and means-tested systems. The latter implies that transfers are conditional on reported means (often income) usually assumed to be either observable or verifiable. Notice that as we assume that some claimants misreport their income in order to be eligible for transfer payments, the term means-testing literally applies only to individuals that truthfully report their income; whereas, in the context of those who misreport their income, we use it to imply means (income) reporting.

  11. By choosing to formulate the government program as one where the government is seeking to minimize the costs associated with a transfer program that aims to attain utility maintenance, we follow the standard approach in the literature (Besley and Coate 1992, 1995 and the subsequent literature referred to in the introduction). An alternative equivalent way of formulating the government program would be to adopt a Rawlsian objective, namely, to maximize the well-being of the least well-off individual, subject to a given budget constraint. We simplify by considering explicitly only the two types that apply for benefits and set aside the public finance issue of how to raise the funds to support the transfer program (by taxing higher-ability individuals).

  12. One could alternatively assume that disutility from misreporting depends on the amount of income sheltered from the welfare agency/tax authority. Our simplifying assumption is made for tractability purposes and could be relaxed without affecting the qualitative nature of our results.

  13. In the absence of misreporting, the government is only faced with a screening problem (high ability individuals ‘cheating’ by mimicking their low-ability counterparts). It is known from the literature that in such a setting one can confine attention to schedules comprised of type-tailored income-consumption bundles, with no loss of generality. In our two-type setting this implies that one can focus on the two bundles assigned to the high-ability and low-ability individuals, respectively. We argue that even when cheating (misreporting income) is accounted for, restricting attention to the two type-tailored bundles is still with no loss of generality. The reason is that reporting of any other level of income effectively exposes the individual as a cheater. Clearly, any misreporting individual (high- or low-ability) will report the level of income assigned to the low-ability individuals.

  14. With no loss in generality we can assume that the high-skill individual participates in the program. This follows, as we can always treat a program in which the high-skill individual does not participate, as one which offers a zero transfer at her choice of income in the absence of a transfer program.

  15. What matters for our results is only the existence of misreporting amongst the high-ability individuals. In this sense the crucial modeling assumption is only about the heterogeneity in psychic costs on the part of high-skilled workers. Indeed, as will become apparent below, the extent of misreporting amongst the low-ability individuals bears no implications on the formulation of the government program.

  16. Notice, that there are, naturally, also low-ability individuals who will choose to misreport in equilibrium (those with least moral inhibitions; namely, those incurring the lowest moral costs). However, as low-ability individuals are in any case entitled to the larger level of benefit, \(\underline {c}-\underline {y}\), this will not affect the government objective and optimization considerations. In this sense, what is essential for our argument is that some misreporting takes place amongst the high-skill individuals. Notice further, that by revealed preference considerations, those individuals who choose to misreport will derive a higher level of utility than that derived by those individuals who report truthfully, thus the individual rationality (voluntary participation) condition will be satisfied and the level of utility will exceed the minimal threshold set by the government also for those who misreport.

  17. To see this, note that the government can set \(\underline {y}\) and \(\overline {y}\) at their levels chosen in the absence of a transfer program, \(\overline {c} = \overline {y}\) and set \(\underline {c}> \underline {y}\) to attain the minimal utility goal. As, in the absence of a transfer program, by revealed preference, the high-skill individual strictly prefers her bundle to the bundle chosen by the low-skill individual, it follows by continuity that when the desired minimum level is small enough, that is when \(\underline {c}\) is sufficiently close to \(\underline {y}\), the self-selection constraint of the high-skill individual will be satisfied and there will be no reason to introduce distortions (in order to mitigate this constraint).

  18. We argue that a major gain from introducing workfare is due to the fact that participating in a workfare program entails particularly high costs for high-skill income-misreporting welfare claimants. Unfortunately, there could be other groups/types targeted by the welfare system that are likely to incur high costs from participating in a workfare program. A case in point is single parents who derive high marginal utility from spending time with their children. To alleviate such concerns, workfare may exempt such claimants as is often the case in existing workfare programs.

References

  • Algan, Y., & Cahuc, P. (2009). Civic virtue and labor market institutions. American Economic Journal: Macroeconomics, 1(1), 111–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akerlof, G. (1978). The economics of tagging as applied to the optimal income tax. American Economic Review, 68, 8–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaudrey, P., Blackorby, C., & Szalay, D. (2009). Taxes and employment subsidies in optimal redistribution programs. American Economic Review, 99, 216–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besley, T., & Coate, S. (1992). Workfare versus welfare incentive arguments for work requirements in poverty-alleviation programs. American Economic Review, 82, 249–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Besley, T., & Coate, S. (1995). The design of income maintenance programs. Review of Economic Studies, 62, 187–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brett, C. (1998). Who should be on workfare? The use of work requirements as part of the optimal tax mix. Oxford Economic Papers, 50, 607–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brett, C. (2005). Bunching, time constraints, and workfare. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 7, 93–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burtless, G. (1986). The work response to guaranteed income: A survey of experimental evidence. In A.H. Munnell (Ed.), Lessons from the income maintenance experiments (pp. 22–52). Boston: Federal Reserve bank of Boston and The Brookings Institution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cremer, H., & Gahvari, F. (1996). Tax evasion and the optimum general income tax. Journal of Public Economics, 60(2), 235–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuff, K. (2000). Optimality of workfare with heterogeneous preferences. Canadian Journal of Economics, 33, 149–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P. (1998). Optimal income taxation: An example with a U-shaped pattern of optimal marginal tax rates. American Economic Review, 88, 83–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fong, C. (2007). Evidence from an experiment on charity to welfare recipients: reciprocity, altruism and the empathic responsiveness hypothesis. Economic Journal, 117(522), 1008–1024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Internal Revenue Service and U.S. Dep’t of the Treasury (2007). Reducing the tax gap: A report on improving voluntary compliance.

  • King, J. (2004). Impediments to gainful employment. Social Security Journal, 66, 9–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kluve, J. (2006). The effectiveness of European active labor market policy (IZA Disc. Paper 2018).

  • Konow, J. (2000). Fair shares: Accountability and cognitive dissonance in allocation decisions. American Economic Review, 90(4), 1072–1091.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luna, E. (1997). Welfare fraud and the fourth amendment. 24 Pepperdine Law Review, 1235, 1250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinelli, C., & Parker, S. (2009). Deception and misreporting in a social program. Journal of the European Economic Association, 7(4), 886–908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirrlees, J. (1971). An exploration in the theory of optimum income taxation. Review of Economic Studies, 38, 175–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moffitt, R. (2006). Welfare work requirements with paternalistic government preferences. Economic Journal, Royal Economic Society, 116(515), F441–F458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, A., & Zeckhauser, R. (1982). Targeting transfers through restrictions on recipients. American Economic Review, 72(2), 372–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • OECD (2005). OECD employment outlook. Paris: OECD.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • OECD (2009). Employment outlook 2009: Tackling the jobs crisis. Paris: OECD.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Romanov, D., & Zussman, N. (2001). Income maintenance and its effects on labor supply and income misreporting. Economics Quarterly, 48, 607–646.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadka, E. (1976). On income distribution, incentive effects and optimal income taxation. Review of Economic Studies, 43, 261–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salanie, B. (2003). The economics of taxation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, F. (2007). Shadow economies and corruption all over the world: New estimates for 145 countries. The Open Access—Open Assessment, E-Journal No. 2007-09.

  • Schneider, F., & Enste, D. (2000). Shadow economies: size, causes, and consequences. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 77–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szilagyi, J. (1990). Where have all the dependents gone? In IRS, 1990 update: Trend analyses and related statistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (2002). TANF: Fourth annual report to congress. Washington: Administration for Children and Families.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, D., & Greenberg, D. (1986). The dynamics of welfare fraud. Journal of Human Resources, 21, 437–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaniv, G. (1997). Welfare fraud and welfare stigma. Journal of Economic Psychology, 18, 435–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank two anonymous referees for helpful comment and constructive suggestions. The usual disclaimer applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Efraim Sadka.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Proof that constraint ( 4 ) is non-binding in the optimal solution

Let \(\hat{u} = \overline {V}\). By virtue of (3), it follows that \(\underline {c}- h(\underline {y}/\underline {w}+\varDelta )\geq \overline {V}\). Thus, \(\underline {c}- h(\underline {y}/\overline {w}+\varDelta )\geq \overline {V}\); hence, by virtue of (5), \(\overline {c}- h(\overline {y}/\overline {w})> \overline {V}\). It follows that the constraint in (4) is satisfied as a strict inequality. By continuity considerations, the result extends to values of \(\hat{u}\) sufficiently close to \(\overline {V}\). This completes the proof.

Proof that constraint ( 5 ) is binding in the optimal solution

Consider first the benchmark case in the absence of misreporting; namely, when \(\overline {\alpha}\to \infty\). In this case we can ignore constraint (7), as the set of individuals who misreport is of zero measure. Suppose by way of contradiction that constraint (5) is not binding. Thus, as constraint (4) is also non-binding (as shown above), then by continuity considerations, one can slightly reduce the level of \(\overline {c}\) without violating any of the constraints (4) and (5). Notice that by reducing the level of \(\overline {c}\) none of the other two constraints ((3) and (6)) is violated either. This slight modification will economize on government expenditure and attain the desired contradiction to the presumed optimality. Consider next the case where a non-zero measure of individuals is misreporting. A reduction in \(\overline {c}\) would have two effects on government expenditure, a mechanical effect and a behavioral one. As in the previous case with no misreporting, a reduction in \(\overline {c}\) would lower the level of government expenditure. However, as can be observed from condition (7), the number of high-ability individuals who misreport would then adjust in equilibrium. In particular, α 0 will increase (that is the number of individuals who misreport will increase). This will result in a corresponding increase in government expenditure, which may all in all increase overall government expenditure. To see why an increase in α 0 will increase the government expenditure (other things equal), note that in the optimal solution it is necessarily the case, that \(\underline {c} - \underline {y} \geq \overline {c} - \overline {y}\). If it were not the case, one could replace the presumably optimal program with a universal system that would offer all agents a lump-sum transfer equal to \(\underline {c} - \underline {y}\), which would trivially satisfy all constraints and reduce total government expenditure. Then it follows from the objective in (2) that when the system is indeed means-tested (that is, \(\underline {c} - \underline {y} > \overline {c} - \overline {y}\)), an increase in α 0 does increase total government expenditure.

The overall impact on government expenditure of the combined mechanical and behavioral effect is generally ambiguous. However, our result in the case of no misreporting extends by continuity consideration to the case where the level of misreporting is sufficiently small, that is, \(\overline {\alpha}\) is sufficiently large. In this case the mechanical effect would prevail.

We will show below that a sufficient condition for the incentive constraint in (5) to be binding in the optimal solution for the government problem is the following:

\(\overline {\alpha} \geq 2 \cdot [[\overline {y}- h(\overline {y}/\overline {w})] -[\underline {y}- h (\underline {y}/\overline {w})]]\), where \(\overline {y}\) and \(\underline {y}\) denote the levels of income chosen by a high-skill and low-skill individuals, respectively in the absence of a transfer program.

Signing the optimal marginal tax rates

Assuming no workfare in place (Δ=0) we turn to verify the standard properties of the (implicit) marginal tax rates embedded in the welfare system. Substituting for the term \((1- \alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha})\) from (9) into (10) and re-arranging yields

$$ h' (\overline {y}/\overline {w}) =\overline {w}.$$
(15)

Thus, we obtain the standard ‘efficiency at the top’ result.

Substituting for the term \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\) from (11) into (12) and re-arranging yields

$$ h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w})/\underline {w} = 1- \mu /\lambda \cdot \bigl[1- h' (\underline {y}/\overline {w})/\overline {w}\bigr].$$
(16)

By virtue of the single crossing property and the fact that the incentive constraint of high-skill individual (constraint (5)) is binding, \(\overline {y}>\underline {y}\). Hence by virtue of (15) and the convexity of h, \(h' (\underline {y}/ \overline {w})/\overline {w}< 1\). It follows that \(h' (\underline {y}/ \underline {w})/\underline {w}\leq 1\) (with strict inequality when μ>0). Thus, the (implicit) marginal tax rate levied on the low-skill individual is strictly positive.

Proof of the proposition

The construction of the proof will be in three stages.

Stage I We first turn to simplify the expression in (14), which is reproduced for convenience:

$$ \partial L/ \partial \varDelta |_{\varDelta =0} = \lambda \cdot h'(\underline {y}/\underline {w})- \mu \cdot h'(\underline {y}/\overline {w}) - \eta \cdot \partial \overline{\overline{V}} / \partial \varDelta |_{\varDelta =0}.$$
(17)

Substituting for the term (μη) from (9) into (11) and re-arranging yields

$$ \lambda =2.$$
(18)

By the definition of \(\overline{\overline{V}}(0)\) and by virtue of (15) it follows that \(\overline{\overline{V}}(0) = \overline {y}-h(\overline {y}/\overline {w})\). Substituting into (7) and re-arranging then yields

$$ \alpha_0 = (\underline {c} - \underline {y})- (\overline {c} - \overline {y}).$$
(19)

Substituting into (13) yields

$$ \eta = -\alpha_0 /\overline {\alpha}.$$
(20)

Employing (18) and (20) to simplify (11) yields

$$ \mu = 1- 2 \alpha_0 / \overline {\alpha}.$$
(21)

Differentiating \(\overline {\overline {V}}\) with respect to Δ, employing the envelope theorem, yields

$$ \partial \overline {\overline {V}} /\partial \varDelta |_{\varDelta = 0} = -\overline {w}.$$
(22)

Substituting into the expression in (14) yields

$$ \partial L/ \partial \varDelta |_{\varDelta = 0} = \lambda \cdot h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w})-\mu \cdot h' (\underline {y}/\overline {w}) + \eta \cdot \overline {w}.$$
(23)

Finally, by employing conditions (12), (18), (20) and (21), following some algebraic manipulations, one can obtain the following simplified form of the expression in (23):

$$ \partial L/ \partial \varDelta |_{\varDelta = 0} = \overline {w}\cdot (1 + \alpha_0 / \overline {\alpha})-2 \cdot (\overline {w}/\underline {w}-1) \cdot h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w}).$$
(24)

Stage II We next derive two useful properties of the optimal system that will be employed in what follows. In order to prove these properties we make the additional technical assumption that h‴≥0. Notice that when h takes an iso-elastic functional form, the assumption implies that the (constant) elasticity of labor supply is bounded above by unity, which is consistent with existing empirical evidence (see, e.g., Salanie 2003).

Lemma

(i) \(\partial (\alpha_{0} /\overline {\alpha})/ \partial \overline {\alpha}<0\), (ii) \(\partial \underline {y}/ \partial \overline {\alpha}<0\).

Proof

(i) Substituting for λ, η and μ from (18), (20) and (21) into (12) and re-arranging yields the following simplified expression:

$$ h'(\underline {y}/\underline {w})/\underline {w} = 1 + \frac{(1-2\alpha_0/\overline {\alpha})\cdot [h' (\underline {y}/\overline {w})/\overline {w}-h'(\underline {y}/\underline {w})/\underline {w}]}{(1+ 2\alpha_0/\overline {\alpha})}.$$
(25)

Fully differentiating the expression in (25) with respect to \(\overline {\alpha}\) and re-arranging yields

(26)

Now suppose by way of contradiction that \(\partial (\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha})/\partial \overline {\alpha}\geq 0\). We will examine separately the case where \(\partial (\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha})/\partial \overline {\alpha}> 0\) and the one in which \(\partial (\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha})/\partial \overline {\alpha}= 0\). Consider first the case where \(\partial (\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha})/\partial \overline {\alpha}> 0\). As h is convex, h‴≥0, by assumption, and \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha} \leq 1/2\), by our earlier derivations (21), it follows that \(\partial \underline {y}/ \partial \overline {\alpha}>0\), otherwise, it is straightforward to verify that the right-hand side of the expression in (26) is positively signed, whereas the left-hand side is negatively signed. Now consider the illustrative figure below, which depicts the optimal solution for the government program in the net income-gross income (c,y) space. We denote by U(w,c,y)≡ch(y/w), the utility derived by an individual of type w with gross income y and net income c. Note first that by the convexity of h, the single crossing property holds and in particular, the indifference curve of the low-ability type is steeper than that of the high-ability type (the slope of the indifference curve is given by MRS(w)=h′(y/w)/w). By virtue of our earlier derivations, conditions (3) and (5) are binding in the optimal solution. Fixing the initial level of \(\overline {\alpha}\), the equilibrium is given by the two bundles depicted as triangles in the figure. Now consider a downward shift in \(\overline {\alpha}\); namely \(\overline {\alpha}' < \overline {\alpha}\). By virtue of our presumption, \(\underline {y}(\overline {\alpha}') < \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\) and \(\alpha_{0}'/ \overline {\alpha}' < \alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\), hence, \(\alpha_{0}' < \alpha_{0}\). By virtue of (15) the gross income level chosen by the high-ability type remains unchanged (at the efficient level). The new equilibrium is then given by the two bundles depicted as squares in the Fig. 1.

Fig. 1
figure 1

The optimal solution for the government problem

By virtue of our earlier derivations, \(h' (\underline {y}, \underline {w})/\underline {w}\geq 1\), thus the slope of the indifference curve of the low-ability type in the initial equilibrium (the triangle lying on the steeper indifference curve) is (weakly) lower than unity. Thus, it follows that \(\underline {c}(\overline {\alpha}')- \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha}')\geq \underline {c}(\overline {\alpha}) -\underline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\). As can be straightforwardly observed from the figure, \(\overline {c}(\overline {\alpha}')- \overline {y}(\overline {\alpha}')< \overline {c}(\overline {\alpha}) -\overline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\). We thus conclude

$$\bigl[\underline {c}(\overline {\alpha}')- \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha}')\bigr]-\bigl[ \overline {c}(\overline {\alpha}') - \overline {y}(\overline {\alpha}')\bigr]>\bigl[\underline {c}(\overline {\alpha}) - \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\bigr]-\bigl[ \overline {c}(\overline {\alpha}) - \overline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\bigr].$$

However, by virtue of (19) the last inequality implies that \(\alpha_{0}' > \alpha_{0}\). We thus obtain the desired contradiction.

We turn next to the other case, where \(\partial (\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha})/ \partial \overline {\alpha} = 0\). As h is convex, h‴≥0, by assumption, and \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\leq 1/2\), by our earlier derivations (21), it follows that \(\partial \underline {y}/\partial \overline {\alpha}= 0\), by virtue of (26), by a similar reasoning to the case examined above. Now consider again a downward shift in \(\overline {\alpha}\); namely \(\overline {\alpha}'< \overline {\alpha}\). By virtue of our presumption, \(\underline {y}(\overline {\alpha}') = \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\) and \(\alpha_{0}'/\overline {\alpha}'= \alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\), hence, \(\alpha_{0}'< \alpha_{0}\). In this case the triangles and the corresponding squares depicted in the figure coincide; that is the two equilibria associated with \(\overline {\alpha}'\) and \(\overline {\alpha}\) are identical. It then follows that

$$\bigl[\underline {c}(\overline {\alpha}') - \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha}')\bigr]- \bigl[\overline {c}(\overline {\alpha}') - \overline {y}(\overline {\alpha}')\bigr]=\bigl[\underline {c}(\overline {\alpha}) - \underline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\bigr]- \bigl[\overline {c}(\overline {\alpha}) - \overline {y}(\overline {\alpha})\bigr].$$

By virtue of (19) the last equality implies that \(\alpha_{0}' = \alpha_{0}\). We thus obtain the desired contradiction, as our presumption implies that \(\alpha_{0}' < \alpha_{0}\).

(ii) This part follows immediately from the expression in (26) and part (i). □

Stage III Our final step would be to provide sufficient conditions for the expression in (24) to be negative, that is, for imposing workfare to be socially desirable as it economizes on government costs.

By virtue of (21) and as the incentive constraint of the high-skill individual is binding, it follows that \(\alpha_{0}/ \overline {\alpha} \leq 1/2\) (ensuring that the Lagrange multiplier associated with the high-skill incentive constraint is non-negative). Employing this inequality condition, it follows that a sufficient condition for the expression in (24) to be negative is

$$ 3/2 \cdot \overline {w} -2 (\overline {w}/ \underline {w}-1)\cdot h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w}) <0.$$
(27)

By part (i) of the lemma, the term \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\) is decreasing with respect to \(\overline {\alpha}\). Suppose that \(\overline {\alpha}\) is sufficiently small such that the term \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\) attains its upper-bound; namely, \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha} =1/2\) (μ=0). For later purposes denote the level of \(\overline {\alpha}\) for which \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha} =1/2\) by \(\overline {\overline {\alpha}}\). As, in this case, the multiplier associated with the high-ability type’s incentive compatibility constraint is equal to zero, it follows from (25) that \(h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w}) = \underline {w}\). Substituting into (27) then yields

$$ 3/2 \cdot \overline {w} - 2 \cdot (\overline {w} - \underline {w})< 0\quad \Longleftrightarrow\quad \overline {w}/\underline {w}>4.$$
(28)

It follows that within the range where the incentive constraint of the high-skill individual is binding (namely, \(\overline {\alpha} \geq \overline {\overline {\alpha}}\), implying indeed by virtue of part (i) of the lemma that \(\alpha_{0} /\overline {\alpha} \leq 1/2\), hence, μ≥0), by continuity considerations, for sufficiently small values of \(\overline {\alpha}\) and sufficiently high wage (skill) ratios, the expression in (27) is negative; hence, the expression in (24) is negative.

Taking the other limiting case, by letting \(\overline {\alpha}\to \infty\), that is, assuming no misreporting, it follows from (18), (20) and (21) that μ=1 and η=0 (and evidently, λ=2). By the convexity of h, \(h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w}) > h' (\underline {y}/\overline {w})\). It thus follows from (23) that ∂L/∂Δ| Δ=0>0. That is, imposing a workfare requirement in the case of no misreporting is undesirable. We thus replicate the result obtained by Besley and Coate (1995). We conclude that the expression in (24), which is a simplified form of (23), is positive. Hence, as \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha}\leq 1/2\), it follows that in the limiting case where \(\overline {\alpha}\to \infty\), hence, by continuity considerations, for sufficiently large values of \(\overline {\alpha}\):

$$ 3/2 \cdot \overline {w} -2 (\overline {w}/\underline {w}-1) \cdot h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w}) >0.$$
(29)

Combining the two (strict) inequality conditions given in (27) and (29), and provided that \(\overline {w}/\underline {w} > 4\), by continuity, it follows by virtue of the intermediate-value theorem that there exists some value of \(\overline {\alpha}\), denoted by \(\overline {\alpha}_{0}\), for which:

$$ 3/2 \cdot \overline {w} - 2 (\overline {w}/\underline {w}-1) \cdot h' (\underline {y}/\underline {w}) =0.$$
(30)

By virtue of part (ii) of the lemma, the expression on the left-hand-side of (30) is strictly increasing with respect to \(\overline {\alpha}\), hence, \(\overline {\alpha}_{0}\) is uniquely defined. Moreover, it follows by part (ii) of the lemma that when the moral costs entailed by misreporting are sufficiently small \((\overline {\overline {\alpha}} \leq \overline {\alpha} < \overline {\alpha}_{0})\), and when the difference between the skill levels is large enough \((\overline {w}/\underline {w}> w_{0} = 4)\), the sufficient condition in (27) holds; hence, imposing workfare is socially desirable as it economizes on government expenditure. This completes the proof.

A sufficient condition for the incentive constraint in ( 5 ) to bind

In the proof of the proposition it is assumed that the incentive constraint in (5) is binding. We turn next to establish a sufficient condition for the incentive constraint in (5) to be binding. We then turn to verify that the range of parameters for which workfare is a desirable supplement to means testing (characterized in stage III of the proof of the proposition) is indeed well defined, by verifying that the incentive constraint of the high-skill individual is binding.

Claim

The following condition suffices for the incentive constraint in (5) to be binding:

$$ \overline {\alpha} \geq 2 \cdot \bigl[ \bigl[\overline {y}-h (\overline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr]- \bigl[\underline {y}-h (\underline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr] \bigr],$$
(31)

where \(\overline {y}\) and \(\underline {y}\) denote the levels of income chosen by a high-skill and low-skill individuals, respectively, in the absence of a transfer program.

Proof

Suppose that there is no workfare requirement in place (as in the statement of the proposition) and suppose further, by way of contradiction, that the condition in (31) holds but the incentive constraint in (5) does not bind. Hence, the Lagrange multiplier associated with the incentive constraint in (5) is equal to zero.

Repeating the steps in Stage I of the proof of the Proposition (see above for details) it follows by virtue of (21) that

$$ \mu = 1 -2 \alpha_0 / \overline {\alpha}.$$
(32)

Hence,

$$ \mu = 0 \quad \Longleftrightarrow\quad \alpha_0/ \overline {\alpha} = 1/2.$$
(33)

By virtue of (15) and (16) it follows that

(34)
(35)

Hence, \(\overline {y}\) denote \(\underline {y}\) the levels of income chosen by high-skill and low-skill individuals, respectively, in the absence of a transfer program.

By virtue of (19) it follows that

$$ \alpha_0 = (\underline {c} -\underline {y}) - (\overline {c} -\overline {y}).$$
(36)

By virtue of the (non-binding, by presumption) incentive constraint in (5) it follows that

$$ \overline {c} - h(\overline {y}/ \overline {w}) > \underline {c} - h \bigl[(\underline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr].$$
(37)

It hence follows that

$$ h \bigl[(\underline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr] - h(\overline {y}/ \overline {w})>\underline {c}-\overline {c}.$$
(38)

Substituting into (36), employing (33) and re-arranging yields

$$ \overline {\alpha} < 2 \cdot \bigl[ \bigl[\overline {y}-h (\overline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr] -\bigl[\underline {y} - h (\underline {y}/ \overline {w})\bigr] \bigr].$$
(39)

As (39) violates (31), we obtain the desired contradiction. This completes the proof. □

Finally, we turn to show that the range of parameters for which workfare is a desirable supplement to means testing is indeed well defined. Recall that in Stage III of the proof of the proposition we have established that for values of \(\overline {\alpha}\) which lie within the range \(\overline {\overline {\alpha}} \leq \overline {\alpha} \leq \overline {\alpha}_{0}\) and for wage ratios that satisfy the condition, \(\overline {w}/\underline {w}>4\), imposing workfare does economize on government costs and is hence socially desirable. Recall further that \(\overline {\overline {\alpha}}\) was defined as the level of \(\overline {{\alpha}}\) for which the incentive constraint of the high-skill individual is binding and μ=0 (hence, \(\alpha_{0}/\overline {\alpha} =1/2\)). When the incentive constraint of the high-skill individual is binding, it follows that

$$ h\bigl[(\underline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr] - h(\overline {y}/\overline {w}) = \underline {c}- \overline {c}.$$
(40)

Substituting for the term \(\underline {c}- \overline {c}\) from (40) into (36) yields:

$$ \alpha_0 = \bigl[\overline {y}- h(\overline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr]- \bigl[\underline {y}- h(\underline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr].$$
(41)

As \(\alpha_{0} / \overline {\overline {\alpha}} = 1/2\), it follows that:

$$ \overline {\overline {\alpha}} = 2 \cdot \bigl[ \bigl[ \overline {y}- h(\overline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr]- \bigl[ \underline {y}- h(\underline {y}/\overline {w})\bigr] \bigr].$$
(42)

Thus, we have established that for the range of parameters for which introducing workfare is socially desirable the incentive constraint of the high-skill individual (given in condition (5)) is indeed binding.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Blumkin, T., Margalioth, Y. & Sadka, E. The desirability of workfare in the presence of misreporting. Int Tax Public Finance 20, 71–88 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10797-012-9215-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10797-012-9215-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation