Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Allocating climate adaptation finance: examining three ethical arguments for recipient control

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Environmental Agreements: Politics, Law and Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most agree that large sums of money should be transferred to the most vulnerable countries in order to help them adapt to climate change. But how should that money be allocated within those countries? A popular and intuitively plausible answer, in line with the strong standing of the norm of ownership in development aid circles, is that this is for the recipient country to decide. The paper investigates the three most important types of ethical arguments for such ‘recipient control’: the epistemic argument, the entitlement argument, and the legitimacy argument. It is argued that there is a good case for recipient control in democratic countries, because such countries can be expected to act in the name of the people to whom adaptation finance is ultimately owed. However, the three arguments do not support, even if taken jointly, recipient control in nondemocratic countries. This is a significant result seeing as the majority of the most vulnerable countries are nondemocratic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘Adaptation finance’ is not a precise term since finance that goes toward socioeconomic development also tends to increase adaptive capacity (Ayers and Dodman 2010; Victor 2011). However, promoting adaptation via official development assistance (ODA) threatens the ‘additional requirement’ of adaptation finance (Füssel et al. 2012; Klein 2011). For the purposes of this paper, I will assume that adaptation finance can be separated from development assistance, either by its separate funding channels or by its focusing on reducing risks that are primarily climate change related.

  2. As laid out by Article 4.8, these factors include that the country has low-lying coastal areas, is liable to drought and desertification, or is prone to natural disasters. Klein (2009) reviews what UNFCCC and associated documents mean by a ‘particularly vulnerable’ country.

  3. These three components of vulnerability are known as exposure, sensitivity, and adaptive capacity (Füssel 2007, 164).

  4. Indeed, Persson and Remling find that the Adaptation Fund does not even at the international level distribute finance on the basis of vulnerability. As they note, ‘approval decisions have not prioritized the most vulnerable countries when they are measured against the current vulnerability indices. Given that per capita concerns do not play an obvious role, it can be concluded that the particular interpretation of international equity as equal lump sums to countries have been dominant today’ (Persson and Remling 2014, 502; cf. Stadelmann et al. 2014).

  5. For an up-to-date overview of the multifaceted world of adaptation finance, see Climate Funds Update’s website: http://www.climatefundsupdate.org/.

  6. This aim is especially visible in the Paris Declaration’s principles of ownership and alignment.

  7. It is of course likely that many transfers taking place under the heading of ‘official development assistance’ are also compensatory, in which case the moral difference between adaptation finance and development aid becomes smaller. I return to this when discussing the entitlement argument.

  8. For overviews of the aid effectiveness literature, see Nissanke (2010) and Sjöstedt (2013).

  9. Another reason is that the recipient is more motivated than others to protect its own interests. As Mill (1998, 245) wrote, ‘the rights and interests of every or any person are only secure from being disregarded, when the person himself is able, and habitually disposed, to stand up for them.’

  10. Operational since 2002, the Least Developed Country Fund is an example of the priority given to LDCs. The Adaptation Fund, however, has so far not expressed this priority (Persson and Remling 2014).

  11. The LDCs classified as being both free and electoral democracies by Freedom House (2013) are Benin, Kiribati, Lesotho, Samoa, São Tomé and Príncipe, Senegal, Sierra Leone, Tuvalu, and Vanuatu.

  12. For practical examples of such bypassing, see Oxfam (2011, 8).

  13. Indeed, unless there is a shared metric against which to judge success or failure, it is not possible to say whether one type of aid is ‘more effective’ than another. Efforts are being made to develop universal metrics of effectiveness in adaptation, see, e.g., Stadelmann et al. (2015).

  14. Crocker (2008, 43f) notes that there is disagreement about the appropriate ends of development aid too. Insofar this is true the objections I raise below could also be raised against epistemic arguments for recipient control over development aid.

  15. Buchanan (2004) calls this general ideal Societal Distributive Autonomy. For defenders, see Crocker (2008, 45), Miller (2007, 74), and Rawls (1999b, 37–38). Since Societal Distributive Autonomy merely establishes a right to noninterference, it can at best be considered a weak argument for recipient control.

  16. What I call ‘duties of aid’ correspond to what Barry calls ‘duties of humanity’ and Valentini calls ‘duties of charity.’

  17. As Barry (2008) notes, this means that duties of justice are more fundamental, for I cannot know what is mine to charitably transfer until I know what my true entitlements are.

  18. Someone has a control right over X if and only if she has (a) a right that others do not use X (a claim right) and (b) a right to use X (a liberty right) (Vallentyne 2012).

  19. It could be argued that duties of justice cannot be generated with respect to large share of total emissions of greenhouse gases because the emitters were excusably ignorant about the harmful effects of these emissions. There is a large debate on whether excusably ignorant emissions negate responsibility (and if so what kinds of responsibility) or only blameworthiness. For a good overview, see Bell (2011).

  20. It might be that climate change puts such great pressure on a society that it is inevitable that the basic rights of some people will remain unfulfilled. Then we might instead say that just methods of triage must be in place (see Page 2007).

  21. This in some ways resembles the guideline setup for the NAPAs (Huq and Khan 2006).

  22. Another way is to work with output-based aid (Mumssen et al. 2010).

  23. Miller (2007, 128–130) notes the possibility that nondemocratic policies could be evaluated according to how well they correspond with beliefs and values that are entrenched in society. However, although such an evaluation is strictly speaking not based on hypothetical consent, it is still epistemically very difficult.

  24. Inglehart (2003) notes, however, that democratic attitudes like tolerance for minorities and respect for civil rights are more variable.

  25. There is a worry that donors will abandon the most vulnerable countries in favor of countries with higher institutional capacity if recipient control is strengthened. Stadelmann et al. (2014) in a study of projects approved by the Adaptation Fund found signs of this.

References

  • Ayers, J., & Dodman, D. (2010). Climate change adaptation and development I: The state of the debate. Progress in Development Studies, 10(2), 161–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baer, P. (2010). Adaptation to climate change: Who pays whom? In S. Gardiner, S. Caney, D. Jamieson, & H. Shue (Eds.), Climate ethics: Essential readings (pp. 247–262). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barr, R., Fankhauser, S., & Hamilton, K. (2010). Adaptation investments: A resource allocation framework. Mitigation and Adaptation Strategies for Global Change, 15(8), 843–858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, S. (2014). Subnational climate justice? Adaptation finance distribution and climate vulnerability. World Development, 58, 130–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (2008). Humanity and justice in global perspective. In T. Pogge & D. Moellendorf (Eds.), Global justice: Seminal essays (pp. 179–209). St Paul: Paragon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumert, K., Herzog, T., & Pershing, J. (2005). Navigating the numbers: Greenhouse gas data and international climate policy. Washington, DC: World Resources Institute.

  • Bell, D. (2011). Global climate justice, historic emissions, and excusable ignorance. The Monist, 94(3), 391–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. (2004). Justice, legitimacy, and self-determination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., & Keohane, R. (2006). The legitimacy of global governance institutions. Ethics & International Affairs, 20(4), 405–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • CDKN. (2013). Enhancing direct access to the green climate fund. Climate & Development Knowledge Network Policy Brief, June 2013. http://cdkn.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/06/CDKN_GCFPolicyBrief_Pr2_21-06-13_WEB.pdf. Accessed November 28, 2014.

  • Ciplet, D., Roberts, T., & Khan, M. (2013). The politics of international climate adaptation funding: Justice and divisions in the greenhouse. Global Environmental Politics, 13(1), 49–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crocker, D. A. (2008). Ethics of global development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duus-Otterström, G., & Jagers, S. (2012). Identifying burdens of coping with climate change: A typology of the duties of climate justice. Global Environmental Change, 22(3), 746–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2011). Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1993). Ethical individualism and presentism. The Monist, 76(3), 333–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedom House. (2013). Freedom in the World 2013. Washington, DC: Freedom House.

  • Füssel, H.-M. (2007). Vulnerability: A generally applicable conceptual framework for climate change research. Global Environmental Change, 17(2), 155–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Füssel, H.-M., Hallgatte, S., & Reder, M. (2012). International adaptation funding. In O. Edenhofer, et al. (Eds.), Climate change, justice and sustainability: Linking climate and development policy (pp. 311–330). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (2007). Enfranchising all affected interests, and its alternatives. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35(1), 40–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grasso, M. (2010). Justice in funding adaptation under the international climate change regime. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hinkel, J. (2011). Indicators of vulnerability and adaptive capacity: Towards a clarification of the science-policy interface. Global Environmental Change, 21(1), 198–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huq, S., & Khan, M. (2006). Equity in national adaptation programs of action: The case of Bangladesh. In N. Adger, J. Paavola, S. Huq & M. Mace (Eds.), Fairness in adaptation to climate change (pp. 181–200). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Hyden, G. (2008). After the Paris Declaration: Taking on the issue of power. Development Policy Review, 26(3), 259–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inglehart, R. (2003). How solid is mass support for democracy—How can we measure it? PS: Political Science and Politics, 36(1), 51–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, R. (2009). Identifying countries that are particularly vulnerable to the adverse effects of climate change: An academic or political challenge? The Carbon & Climate Law Review, 3(3), 284–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, R. (2011). Linking adaptation and development: A policy dilemma not addressed in Copenhagen. Climate and Development, 2(3), 203–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1998). On liberty and other essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2007). National responsibility and global justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, B. (2011). Enhanced direct access. Oxford: Oxford Institute for Energy Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, B. (2014). Enhancing direct access and country ownership. Oxford: Oxford Institute for Energy Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumssen, Y., Johannes, L. & Kumar, G. (2010). Output-based aid: Lessons and best practices. Washington, DC: The World Bank.

  • Nissanke, M. (2010). Reconstructing the aid effectiveness debate. In G. Mavrotas (Ed.), Foreign aid for development: Issues, challenges, and the new agenda (pp. 63–93). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Oxfam. (2011). Owning adaptation. Country-level governance of climate adaptation finance. Oxfam briefing paper 146. Available at http://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/bp146-owning-adaptation-130611-en.pdf. Accessed February 2, 2014.

  • Paavola, J., & Adger, N. (2006). Fair adaptation to climate change. Ecological Economics, 56(4), 594–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Page, E. (2007). Justice between generations: Investigating a sufficientarian approach. Journal of Global Ethics, 3(1), 3–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, Å., & Remling, E. (2014). Equity and efficiency in adaptation finance: Initial experiences of the adaptation fund. Climate Policy, 14(4), 488–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peter, F. (2010). Political legitimacy. In Zalta, E. (Ed.). The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/libertarianism. Accessed February 2, 2014.

  • Plato. (2000). The Republic. Transl. T. Griffith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Pogge, T. (2008). World poverty and human rights (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999a). A theory of justice, revised edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999b). The law of peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sjöstedt, M. (2013). Aid effectiveness and the Paris Declaration: A mismatch between ownership and results-based management? Public Administration and Development, 33(2), 143–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stadelmann, M., Michaelowa, A., Butzengeiger-Geyer, S., & Köhler, M. (2015). Universal metrics to compare the effectiveness of climate change adaptation projects. In W. Leal Filho (Ed.), Handbook of climate change adaptation. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadelmann, M., Persson, Å., Ratajczak-Juszko, I., & Michaelowa, A. (2014). Equity and cost-effectiveness of multilateral adaptation finance: Are they friends or foes? International Environmental Agreements: Politics, Law and Economics, 14(2), 101–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stilz, A. (2010). Collective responsibility and the state. Journal of Political Philosophy, 19(2), 190–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, L. (2013). Justice, charity, and disaster relief: What, if anything, is owed to Haiti, Japan and New Zealand? American Journal of Political Science, 57(2), 491–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallentyne, P. (2012). Libertarianism. In Zalta, E. (Ed). The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/libertarianism. Accessed February 2, 2014.

  • Victor, D. (2011). Global warming gridlock. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Kerkhoff, L., Ahman, I. H., Pittock, J. & Steffen, W. (2011). Designing the green climate fund: How to spend $100 billion sensibly. Environment. May-June issue, 2011.

  • Zürn, M. (2004). Global governance and legitimacy problems. Government and Opposition, 39(2), 260–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Previous versions of this paper have been presented at the 6th Uppsala Forum Workshop on Climate Change, at the Centre for Global Democratic Governance at the University of St. Gallen, and at the 17th Nordic Political Science Association congress at the University of Gothenburg. I am grateful to the audiences at all those occasions, as well as to the two anonymous referees, for helpful comments. The paper has been written within the project ‘Fair and Feasible Climate Change Adaptation,’ which is co-financed by the Swedish Research Council and Formas.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Göran Duus-Otterström.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duus-Otterström, G. Allocating climate adaptation finance: examining three ethical arguments for recipient control. Int Environ Agreements 16, 655–670 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10784-015-9288-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10784-015-9288-3

Keywords

Navigation