Skip to main content
Log in

Whatever You Want? Beyond the Patient in Medical Law

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Simon Woods proposes that we ought to re-orientate clinical decisions at the end of life back towards the patient, so as to honour his or her account of their “global” interests. Woods condemns the current medico-legal approach for remaining too closely tethered to the views of doctors. In this response, I trace the story of Mrs Kelly Taylor, who sought to be sedated and have life-sustaining treatment withdrawn, and I do so in order to show not only why Woods is right to detect an asymmetry in the law but also why there is more to the legal landscape than first appears. I argue that patient choice is indeed bounded—most obviously by the views of the doctors (and the judges), but no less significantly by so-called “public interest” concerns. Woods’ proposal implicitly, and rightly, forces reconsideration of these public interest dimensions of medico-legal decision-making. This often invisible boundary is not presently granted the attention it deserves (not least by the judges themselves). However, as soon as we delve into the ethical values at stake, then it becomes apparent that there are many more questions to be asked regarding their meaning and interaction before we can determine the appropriate ethical prism through which to view the health care endeavour in English medical law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is evidence that British citizens are taking up the option to receive assistance in suicide in Switzerland. The precise legality of this practice is in doubt, particularly for friends or relatives who help the person to travel abroad: see, for further discussion [17, pp. 63–66].

  2. The lawful permission granted to fatal inaction [1] will not be directly considered at this juncture.

  3. This is not to say that all such decisions have been respected. Sometimes the judges are inclined to override a particular decision to decline food—and there is reason to suspect that undisclosed policy factors can prove determinative, as John Coggon has argued [7, pp. 249–250]. I will return to the policy (or public interest) dimensions of medico-legal reasoning later in this paper.

  4. For example, see [6, 33].

  5. For a more detailed argument to this effect, see [17, p. 76].

  6. Not only might we reasonably assume that they would have learned of her decision in the course of their ongoing relationship with her, but she also publicised her decision in the local and national media.

  7. Note, for example, the Mental Capacity Act 2005 and the earlier leading rulings in Re F [34] and Re A [32].

  8. Note, for example, the letters prompted by the discussion in [25].

  9. But see also [36], discussed in [17, pp. 65–66].

  10. My central point here is that the lawfulness of Mrs Taylor’s request depends, at least in part, on the doctor(s) being willing to act on her request. I should add that the (conscientious) objections of Mrs Taylor’s current doctors are afforded a place in law [33]. However, where clinicians do object to involvement with a lawful request, they are duty-bound to refer care of the patient onto clinicians who are willing to comply. This suggests that there is more to the interplay between the views of the doctors and the decision as to lawfulness than I can explore in this paper.

  11. Certainly, the judges seldom spell out the meaning or content of the public interest, despite their (occasionally explicit) appeals to the concept. The absence of critical engagement with this notion is even mirrored in the academic literature—scholars will frequently consider the ethical and policy dimensions of a particular topic (like euthanasia), but will less often step back and consider the broader scope of the public interest in medical law. Fortunately, the trend is starting to reverse, with important contributions now being made by bioethicists [3] and medical lawyers [21].

  12. Autonomy in the “relevant” legal sense will be further considered below.

  13. There are, however, undoubtedly other examples that could be given, such as the latitude sometimes afforded to clinicians through reliance on (or deference to) clinical judgement. Thus, we see rulings in which the views of the clinicians occasionally take precedence over other values and interests, such as those held by the patient or their proxy [18]. There are also situations in which the judges have had cause to consider the scope that should be afforded to the integrity (and consciences) of individual clinicians: see e.g. note 10.

  14. Although there is insufficient space to consider the possibilities in detail, it is worth briefly noting the questions that need to be asked. As such, is the protection premised on some form of contract between the doctor and the patient? Or is the relationship, and the associated entitlements and responsibilities, premised on a convenantal relationship? Or is it the nature of the doctor’s duty that entails the acquisition of special privileges? For consideration of some of these questions, see e.g. [41, 17, pp. 128–130].

  15. Consider the competing interpretations given to the Dutch data on euthanasia by e.g. Keown [19] and Otlowski [23].

  16. I have argued elsewhere that such claims are rarely convincing [15], even in seemingly unusual cases like the decision to authorise the separation of conjoined twins [31]—indeed, that very ruling was soon applied in an Australian case [24].

  17. Indeed, it will always be necessary to subject what Harrington calls the “distinctively judicial common sense” to external scrutiny [14].

References

  1. Airedale NHS Trust v Bland. (1993). 2 WLR 816.

  2. Anonymous. (2007). Terminally ill woman seeks right to die. The Guardian (12/02/2007).

  3. Ashcroft, R. E. (2004). From public interest to political justice. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 13, 20–27.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Bolam v Friern Hospital Management Committee. (1957). 1 WLR 582.

  5. Bolitho v City and Hackney Health Authority. (1997). 4 All ER 771.

  6. Chatterton v Gerson. (1981). 1 All ER 257.

  7. Coggon, J. (2007). Varied and principled understandings of autonomy in English law: Justifiable inconsistency or blinkered moralism? Health Care Analysis, 15, 235–255.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. D v UK. (1997). ECHR 25.

  9. Devlin, P. (1985). Easing the passing: The trial of Dr Bodkin Adams. London: Bodley Head.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Dyer, C. (2007). Allow me to die, terminally ill woman urges court. The Guardian (13/02/2007).

  11. Fenton, B. (2007). Woman fights for ‘right to die’. The Daily Telegraph (13/02/2007).

  12. Halliday, R. (1997). Medical futility and the social context. Journal of Medical Ethics, 23, 148–153.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  13. Harrington, J. A. (1996). Privileging the medical norm: Liberalism, self-determination and refusal of treatment. Legal Studies, 16, 348–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Harrington, J. (2003). Deciding best interests: Medical progress, clinical judgment and the ‘good family’. Web JCLI, 3.

  15. Huxtable, R. (2001). Logical separation? Conjoined twins, slippery slopes and resource allocation. Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law, 23(4), 459–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Huxtable, R. (2004). Case commentary: Re C (a child)(immunisation: Parental rights) [2003] EWCA Civ 114. Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law, 26(1), 69–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Huxtable, R. (2007). Euthanasia, ethics and the law: From conflict to compromise. London: Routledge-Cavendish.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Jackson, L., & Huxtable, R. (2005). The doctor–parent relationship: As fragile as glass? Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law, 27(3–4), 369–381.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Keown, J. (2002). Euthanasia, ethics and public policy: An argument against legalisation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Laurance, J. (2007). Woman goes to court in historic euthanasia case. The Independent (13/02/2007).

  21. Laurie, G., & Mason, J. K. (2008). Medicine, law and the public interest: Communitarian perspectives in medical law. London: Routledge-Cavendish.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Marinko, P. (2005). Euthanasia law forces woman to starve to death. The Guardian (04/08/05).

  23. Otlowski, M. F. A. (1997). Voluntary euthanasia and the common law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Queensland v Nolan. (2001). QSC 174.

  25. Quill, T. E., & Byock, I. R. (2000). Responding to intractable terminal suffering: The role of terminal sedation and voluntary refusal of food and fluids. Annals of International Medicine, 132, 408–414.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  26. R v Adams. (1957). Crim LR 365.

  27. R v Brown et al. (1993). 2 All ER 75.

  28. R (Burke) v GMC. (2005). 3 WLR 1132.

  29. R v Moor. (2000). Crim LR 31.

  30. R (on the application of Pretty) v DPP. (2002). 1 FLR 268.

  31. Re A (children)(conjoined twins: Surgical separation). (2000). 4 All ER 961.

  32. Re A (Male sterilisation). (2000). 1 FLR 549.

  33. Re B (Adult: Refusal of medical treatment). (2002). 2 All ER 449.

  34. Re F (a mental patient: Sterilisation). (1990). 2 AC 1.

  35. Re MB (Medical treatment). (1997). 2 FLR 426.

  36. Re Z (Local authority: Duty). (2005). 1 WLR 959.

  37. Savill, R. (2005). Woman ends ‘right to die’ food protest. The Daily Telegraph (13/08/2005).

  38. Savill, R. (2007). ‘Right to die’ patient to fight for choice. The Daily Telegraph (24/04/2007).

  39. Secretary of State for the Home Department v Robb. (1995). Fam. 127.

  40. Smith, J. C. (2000). A comment on Moor’s case. Criminal Law Review, 41–44.

  41. Stirrat, G. M., & Gill, R. (2005). Autonomy in medical ethics after O’Neill. Journal of Medical Ethics, 31, 127–130.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author gratefully acknowledges the comments made by participants at both the Cardiff symposium and the Centre for Ethics in Medicine (University of Bristol) Journal Club, at which these arguments were presented. Thanks also to Professor Karen Forbes, for stimulating discussions about the legal and ethical issues raised by Mrs Kelly Taylor’s narrative. The author is a member of the Clinical Ethics Advisory Group of the Bristol Royal Infirmary, United Bristol Healthcare NHS Trust. The arguments developed in this paper are the author’s own, and do not express the views of the Committee or the Trust; the author also hopes that nothing in the paper will cause distress to anyone involved in Mrs Taylor’s care.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Huxtable.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Huxtable, R. Whatever You Want? Beyond the Patient in Medical Law. Health Care Anal 16, 288–301 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-008-0082-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-008-0082-z

Keywords

Navigation