Skip to main content
Log in

The Role of Symmetry in Mathematics

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Over the past few decades the notion of symmetry has played a major role in physics and in the philosophy of physics. Philosophers have used symmetry to discuss the ontology and seeming objectivity of the laws of physics. We introduce several notions of symmetry in mathematics and explain how they can also be used in resolving different problems in the philosophy of mathematics. We use symmetry to discuss the objectivity of mathematics, the role of mathematical objects, the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics and the relationship of mathematics to physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For philosophical introductions to symmetry see the Introduction in Brading and Castellani (2003), Brading and Castellani (2007), Brading and Castellani (2013) and Bangu (2012). For a popular introduction to the physical issues see Lederman and Hill (2004). For an interesting philosophical view of symmetry in biology see Bailly and Longo (2011). One should also read Longo (2015) for a fascinating perspective about symmetry in modern mathematics.

  2. See Bangu (2008) for a related discussion of the discovery of the \(\Omega ^{-}\) particle.

  3. Whether or not there are laws of nature at all or whether they should be eliminated in favor of symmetries is a matter of considerable controversy among philosophers of science. See van Fraassen (Van Fraassen 1989; Earman 2004) for stronger and weaker versions of eliminationist views on this issue. Our account is agnostic about this.

  4. The function of variables (and types) have a long and interesting history. We are not saying that the reason for their creation was to foster the notion of symmetry of semantics. However, variables as they are now, are helpful for dealing with symmetry of semantics. For more on the history of variables and symbols in mathematics see Mazur (2014), Heeffer and van Dyck (2010) and Serfati (2005).

  5. Frege’s influence on this definition should be evident. A finite number for Frege consists of the equivalence class of the finite sets where two sets are equivalent if there is an isomorphism from one set to another. When we talk of the equivalence class 5 we are ignorant of the set of the equivalence class under discussion; we may be talking about 5 apples or 5 cars.

  6. Steiner (Steiner 2005) treats those fields as applications of mathematics.

  7. Exactness comes from the fact that there are no counterexamples. This, in turn, leads to symbolization in mathematics. If we can replace one entity by another, we might as well call the entity x.

  8. Various authors (e.g. Steiner 1998; Fillion 2012) now distinguish between various problems of the applicability of mathematics. We confine our remarks to what we take to be Wigner’s (1967) original question of why mathematics can be used at all with respect to the physical world.

  9. Philip Kitcher (e.g. Kitcher 1976) touts the importance of these types of cases for mathematics and uses them in the service of demonstrating the existence of mathematical explanation. Emily Grosholz has studied domain unifications in mathematics extensively. See e.g. Grosholz (2000).

  10. For more about the relationship of category theory and invariance of syntax of semantics see the appendix of Yanofsky and Zelcer (2013). See also Krömer (2007) and Marquis (2009) for more on the history and philosophy of category theory and it relationship to symmetry.

References

  • Azzouni, J. (2005). Is there still a sense in which mathematics can have foundations? In G. Sica (Ed.), Essays on the foundations of mathematics and logic. Italy: Polimetrica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailly, Francis, & Longo, Giuseppe. (2011). Mathematics and the natural sciences: The physical singularity of life., Advances in computer science and engineering London: Imperial College Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2008). Reifying mathematics? Prediction and symmetry classification. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39, 239–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2012). Symmetry. In R. Batterman (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of physics, chapter 8 (pp. 287–317). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965) What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review, lxxiv:47–73. Reprinted in [10].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 70:661–680. Reprinted in [10].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P., & Putnam, H. (Eds.). (1983). Philosophy of mathematics: Selected readings (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brading, K., & Castellani, E. (Eds.). (2003). Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brading, K., & Castellani, E. (2007). Symmetries and invariances in classical physics. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: Philosophy of physics (pp. 1331–1364). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brading, K., & Castellani, E. (2013) Symmetry and symmetry breaking. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Spring 2013 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/symmetry-breaking/

  • Earman, John. (2004). Laws, symmetry, and symmetry breaking: Invariance, conservation principles, and objectivity. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1227–1241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epp, S. S. (2011). Variables in mathematics education. In P. Blackburn, H. van Ditmarsch, M. Manzano, & F. Soler-Toscano (Eds.), Tools for teaching logic (pp. 54–61). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (1967). The character of physical law. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillion, N. (2012). The reasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Ph.D. thesis, The University of Western Ontario.

  • Frenkel, E. (2013). Love and math: The heart of hidden reality. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, G. (1953). Dialogue concerning the two chief world systems. Berkeley, Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz, E. R. (2000). The partial unification of domains, hybrids, and the growth of mathematical knowledge. In E. Grosholz & H. Breger (Eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge (pp. 81–91). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heeffer, A., & van Dyck, M. (Eds.). (2010). Philosophical aspects of symbolic reasoning in early modern mathematics. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1976). Explanation, conjunction, and unification. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 207–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krömer, R. (2007). Tool and object: A history and philosophy of category theory. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawvere, W. (1964). An elementary theory of the category of sets. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 52, 1506–1511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, L., & Hill, C. T. (2004). Symmetry and the beautiful universe. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G. (2015). Synthetic philosophy of mathematics and natural sciences, conceptual analyses from a grothendieckian perspective: Reflections on synthetic philosophy of contemporary mathematics. Speculations: Journal of Speculative Realism, (VI), 207–267.

  • Marquis, J.-P. (1995). Category theory and the foundations of mathematics: Philosophical excavations. Synthese, 103(3), 421–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, J.-P. (2009). From a geometrical point of view: A study of the history and philosophy of category theory. Logic, epistemology and the unity of science. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazur, J. (2014). Enlightening symbols: A short history of mathematical notation and its hidden powers. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Serfati, Michel. (2005). La Révolution symbolique. La constitution de l’écriture symbolique mathématique. Paris: Éditions Pétra.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, Mark. (1995). The applicabilities of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 3(3), 129–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, Mark. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (2005). Mathematics—Application and applicability. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic, chapter 20 (pp. 625–650). New York: Oxford Univ.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stenger, Victor. (2006). The comprehensible cosmos: Where do the laws of physics come from?. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, Bas C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1992). Dreams of a final theory. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), February 1960. Reprinted in Symmetries and Reflections. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1967.

  • Yanofsky, N. S. (2010). Galois theory of algorithms. arXiv:hep-lat/1011.0014.

  • Yanofsky, N. S., & Zelcer, M. (2013). Mathematics via symmetry. arXiv:hep-lat/1306.4235v1.

  • Zee, A. (1990). The effectiveness of mathematics in fundamental physics. In R. E. Mickens (Ed.), Mathematics and Science (pp. 307–323). Singapore: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We wish to thank our friend and mentor Distinguished Professor Rohit Parikh for helpful conversations and for much warm encouragement. Thanks also to Jody Azzouni, Sorin Bangu, Nicolas Fillion, André Lebel, Jim Lambek, Guisseppe Longo, Jean-Pierre Marquis, Jolly Mathen, Alan Stearns, Andrei Rodin, Mark Steiner, Robert Seely, K. Brad Wray, Gavriel Yarmish, and four anonymous referees, who were all extremely helpful commenting on earlier drafts. N. Y. would also like to thank Jim Cox and Dayton Clark for many stimulating conversations on these topics. He acknowledges support for this project from a PSC-CUNY Award, jointly funded by The Professional Staff Congress and The City University of New York. This work was also supported by a generous “Physics of Information” grant from The Foundational Questions Institute (FQXi).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Zelcer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yanofsky, N.S., Zelcer, M. The Role of Symmetry in Mathematics. Found Sci 22, 495–515 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-016-9486-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-016-9486-7

Keywords

Navigation