Skip to main content
Log in

Principle-Based Moral Judgement

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is widely acknowledged that moral principles are not sufficient to guide moral thought and action: they need to be supplemented by a capacity for judgement. However, why can we not rely on this capacity for moral judgement alone? Why do moral principles need to be supplemented, but are not supplanted, by judgement? So-called moral particularists argue that we can, and should, make moral decisions on a case-by-case basis without any principles. According to particularists, the person of moral judgement is a person of empathy, sensibility and virtue, rather than a person of principle. In this paper I argue that this is a false dichotomy. The person of good moral judgement is a person of principle. I propose that we think of moral principles as internalised long-term commitments that form our moral character and sensitivity, and, as such, are constitutive of moral judgement.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. David McNaughton’s view has changed considerably. Cf. McNaughton 1996, McNaughton and Piers Rawling 2000.

  2. For a helpful taxonomy of the different forms of particularism see McKeever and Ridge 2006, 3–24.

  3. It is notoriously difficult to distinguishing the moral from the non-moral. However, I will assume that we have an intuitive grasp of the distinction and will refer to those judgements that fall clearly in the moral realm.

  4. For example, Dancy introduces his Ethics without Principles as a “book […] about how to understand the way in which reasons work” (2004, 7). Similarly, Pekka Väyrynen defines particularism and generalism as “metaphysical doctrines about the role of moral principles regarding the status of certain facts as moral reasons“ (2004, 67). However, a closer look at the literature shows that the current particularist/generalist debate is also a debate about moral reasoning. Dancy starts his book by exploring different ways of “understanding the way in which moral reasoning might work” (2004, 9), and his characterisation of particularism as the thesis that “the possibility of moral thought and judgement does not depend on the provision of a suitable supply of moral principles” (ibid. 7) is open to both a metaphysical and an epistemological reading.

  5. Also see Dancy 2004, 71–117; Väyrynen 2006.

  6. Sean McKeever and Michael Ridge, for example, have successfully shown that even strong, traditional forms of principled ethics such as utilitarianism can account for the fact moral reasons function holistically (cf. 2006, 27–32). In addition it has been shown that it is not only the case that generalists can be holists, particularists can also be atomists. The debate between atomists and holists in the theory of reasons is thus orthogonal to the debate about whether morality can and should be understood in terms of principles (cf. Albertzart 2011, 53–55).

  7. McKeever and Ridge, for example, argue for a form of moral principles that fulfils all of Dancy’s conditions for a principled ethics. Cf. Dancy 2004, 116–117; McKeever and Ridge 2006.

  8. For further discussion see Albertzart 2011.

  9. This fits well with recent empirical work in moral psychology. Cf. Prinz 2007, 272.

  10. By describing moral judgement in perceptual terms, particularists sometimes give the impression that all moral judging is something done in the blink of an eye. Generalists are in a much better situation to acknowledge that there are many difficult decisions which require a conscious process of careful moral reasoning. However, since this is a paper about the capacity of moral judgement and not the process of moral reasoning, it would go beyond the scope of this paper to try to offer a principle-based model of moral reasoning.

  11. By contrast, many particularists and their generalist interlocutors conceive of moral principles as descriptive, truth-apt and explanatory propositions. Dancy claims that the function of moral principles is to fix the truth conditions of moral judgements by determining the moral status of actions (2004, 116). McKeever and Ridge believe that moral principles “provide the truth-conditions for the application of a moral concept” (2006, 7). Similarly, Pekka Väyrynen holds that a moral principle is a “proposition that identifies conditions or properties in virtue of which something has a given moral property such as rightness, and which are thus explanatory of why it is right” (2008, 76). Thus understood moral principles seem to be ‘word to world’ directed and it is much more difficult to see why the acquirement of a rich set of moral sensibilities would not render such principles superfluous.

  12. Given their commitment to cognitivism some particularists might be uneasy about taking this route. Cf. Dancy 2004, 140–141. For alternative views see Roeser 2006, 33–44; Döring 2007, 363–394.

  13. This fits well with recent empirical work in moral psychology. Cf. Nichols 2004; Prinz 2007.

  14. This is a thought that can also be found in Kant’s moral philosophy and has recently been developed by Christine Korsgaard. According to Korsgaard, “the principles of practical reason are principles by means of which we constitute ourselves as unified agents” (2009, 25; cf. Korsgaard 1996, 363–397). I do not mean to commit myself to the details of Korsgaard’s account, in particular the purely rationalist approach that makes it difficult to account for the emotional component of principle-based moral judgement I alluded to earlier.

  15. In most cases more than one act-token will be appropriate.

  16. When particularists insist that moral principles are incompatible with context-sensitivity they usually have a different form of context-sensitivity in mind. They are concerned about cases where a particular act-token seems permissible even though there is a moral principle according to which actions of this type are forbidden. In some contexts lying is morally forbidden, for example, but in others it is not. Pointing to the indeterminacy of moral principles will not help to answer this problem. It is the defeasibility of moral principles that is at issue here. A discussion of the defeasibility of moral principles would require an in-depth discussion of reasons-holism and the development of an account of moral reasoning as default reasoning, which would go beyond the scope and purpose of this paper. For discussion see Horty 2007; Lance and Little 2008.

  17. Cf. Dancy 2004, 141: “The basic reason-facts which we are to come to know are particular; their purview is initially restricted to the particular case. We need to be able to come to know these non-general facts, or to acquire justified beliefs about them; and our knowledge of them will be our basic normative knowledge.”

  18. I borrow this analogy from Joshua Greene. See Greene, “Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality,” Talk, Harvard University, Cambridge, Mass. 17. 02. 2011.

  19. This does not mean that an agent’s understanding of these facts is divorced from, or prior to, what it is to be an agent. I argued that undertaking a commitment shapes an agent’s experiences and sensibilities. An agent might be unable to fully understand certain social and cultural facts about a society, for example, unless she has certain commitments such as a commitment for the welfare of some members of that society or a commitment to social justice. Our commitments shape who we are and how we see the world.

  20. To say that a moral principle needs to be consistent with an agent’s overall system of moral and non-moral commitments is not to say that there can be no moral dilemmas. Moral principles can conflict contingently but not intrinsically (cf. O’Neill 1996, 158–161). Principles that conflict intrinsically can never be simultaneously instantiated. Principles that do not conflict intrinsically are consistent and can be jointly instantiated in at least some circumstances. However, such principles may nevertheless give rise to contingent conflicts: telling the truth will sometimes (but not always) hurt somebody, and saving a life can sometimes (but not always) require a lie. These contingent conflicts are conflicts not between principles but between ways of living up to the principles in particular circumstances. That is, they are conflicts not between the act-types prescribed by moral principles but conflicts between particular tokens of these act-types. Moral conflicts and dilemmas are the result of the particular, contingent circumstances in which an agent finds herself.

  21. This does not mean that we could not adopt a similar principle as a moral ideal. We could commit ourselves to strive towards the ideal of being able to help all those in need. However, the above principle requires us to actually help all those in need, and we should not commit ourselves to doing something we know we cannot do.

References

  • Adams RM (1976) Motive utilitarianism. J Philos 73:467–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albertzart M (2011) Missing the target: Jonathan Dancy’s conception of a principled ethics. J Value Inq 45:49–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe GEM (2000) Intention, first published 1957. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (2000) In: Crisp R (ed) Nicomachean ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Blum L (1991) Moral perception and particularity. Ethics 101:701–725

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (1987) Intention, plans, and practical reason. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman M (2007) Reflection, planning and temporally extended agency. In: Structures of Agency. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 21–46

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (1983) Ethical particularism and morally relevant properties. Mind 92:530–547

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (1993) Moral reasons. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (1999) Can the particularist learn the difference between right and wrong? In: Brinkmann K (ed) The proceedings of the twentieth world congress of philosophy. Vol. 1 Ethics. Philosophy Documentation Center, Bowling Green, pp 59–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy J (2004) Ethics without principles. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Döring SA (2007) Seeing what to do: affective perception and rational motivation. Dialectica 61:363–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan O (1991) Varieties of moral personality. Ethics and psychological realism. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfield J (2000) Particularity and principle: the structure of moral knowledge. In: Hooker B, Little MO (eds) Moral particularism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 178–204

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleeson A (2007) Moral particularism reconfigured. Philos Investig 30:363–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AH (2002) Practical rules. When we need them and when we don’t. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene J, Haidt J (2002) Where (and how) does moral judgement work. Trends Cognit Sci 6:517–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail. Psychol Rev 108:814–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare RM (1963) Freedom and reason. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker B (2000) Ideal code, real world. A rule-consequentialist theory of morality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Horty JF (2007) Reasons as defaults. Philosophers’ Imprint 7:1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1998) In: Guyer P, Wood AW (eds) Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard C (1996) Personal identity and the unity of agency: a Kantian response to Parfit. In: Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 363–397

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard C (2009) Self-constitution. Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lance MN, Little MO (2008) From particularism to defeasibility in ethics. In: Lance MN, Potrc M, Strahovnik V (eds) Challenging moral particularism. Routledge, New York, pp 53–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Larmore CE (1987) Patterns of moral complexity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon R, Nichols S (2010) Rules. In: Doris JM, the Moral Psychology Research Group (eds) The moral psychology handbook. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 297–320

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1998) Virtue and Reason. In: Mind, value, and reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 50–73

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1978) Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives? Proc Aristot Soc, Supplementary Volumes 52:13–29

    Google Scholar 

  • McKeever S, Ridge M (2006) Principled ethics. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton D (1988) Moral vision. An introduction to ethics. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton D (1996) An unconnected heap of duties. Philos Q 46:433–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton D, Rawling P (2000) Unprincipled Ethics. In: Hooker B, Little MO (eds) Moral particularism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 256–275

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1998) Utilitarianism. In: Crisp R (ed) Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Moore GE (1993) Principia Ethica. Revised edition. Baldwin T (ed) Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Nichols S (2004) Sentimental rules. On the foundations of moral judgment. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2001) The fragility of goodness. Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. Revised edition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill O (1996) Towards justice and virtue. A constructive account of practical reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz JJ (2007) The emotional construction of morals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser S (2006) A particularist epistemology: affectual intuitionism. Acta Anal 21:33–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1991) Playing by the rules. A philosophical examination of rule-based decision-making in law and in life. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnall S et al (2008) Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 34:1096–1109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (2004) Particularism and default reasons. Ethical Theory and Moral Pract 7:53–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (2006) Moral generalism: enjoy in moderation. Ethics 116:707–741

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (2008) Usable moral principles. In: Lance MN et al (eds) Challenging moral particularism. Routledge studies in ethics and moral theory. Routledge, New York, pp 75–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman JD (2007) Practical reflection. First published 1989. Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Hallvard Lillehammer, Niklas Möller, Onora O’Neill and two anonymous referees of this journal for their very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maike Albertzart.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Albertzart, M. Principle-Based Moral Judgement. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 16, 339–354 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9343-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9343-x

Keywords

Navigation