Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic Contrastivism, Knowledge and Practical Reasoning

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Epistemic contrastivism is the view that knowledge is a ternary relation between a person, a proposition and a set of contrast propositions. This view is in tension with widely shared accounts of practical reasoning: be it the claim that knowledge of the premises is necessary for acceptable practical reasoning based on them or sufficient for the acceptability of the use of the premises in practical reasoning, or be it the claim that there is a looser connection between knowledge and practical reasoning. Given plausible assumptions, epistemic contrastivism implies that we should cut all links between knowledge and practical reasoning. However, the denial of any such link requires additional and independent arguments; if such arguments are lacking, then all the worse for epistemic contrastivism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the sake of simplicity, I will often express myself here as if there is only one contrast proposition. Nothing of any substance depends on this simplification.

  2. There are other possible views but they lack plausibility and need not be discussed here.

  3. I am putting aside two types of special cases: cases where the target proposition p has no contrast q such that the subject knows that p rather than q, and cases where the target proposition p has no contrast q such that the subject does not know that p rather than q.

  4. Absoluteness in this sense is compatible with contrastivity. What matters is the uniqueness and invariance (with contrast sets) of the answer to the question “What is the right way to think about this and what should I do?”.

  5. Sure, given one standard of cleanliness Fred might count as having removed all of the liquid while given another standard of cleanliness he might not count as such. However, this is not the issue here. The problem above remains even for fixed standards of cleanliness.

  6. See Sinnott-Armstrong (2006, esp. chs. 5 and 6) who does not defend contrastivism about all-things-considered reasons even though he defends contrastivism about justified moral belief. See also Snedegar (2013b, fn. 2) for this restriction of contrastivism to pro tanto reasons.

  7. See also Jordan (2014) who argues that virtue-ethical motivations are not compatible with contrastivism about practical reasons.

  8. Finally, there might be an infinite number of contrast propositions to consider or, at least, an indefinite number. How should we, under such conditions, ever get any grip on what the practically relevant alternative could be?

  9. See for a similar problem about moral justification my 2008.

  10. I won’t explain this further here in order to avoid repetitions—What if one said that practical reasoning based on a given proposition p is better (worse) the more (fewer) contrast propositions q there are such that the subject knows p, rather than q (thanks to a referee for this idea)? There are difficult questions about how to count contrast propositions and how to weigh their relative importance. Apart from that, this is not quite the proposal under discussion, namely that knowledge (construed contrastively or not) of a proposition improves the quality of practical reasoning based on it; this is rather the idea that “more knowledge” improves the quality of practical reasoning. However, this “additional” knowledge does not affect whether the subject knows the relevant target proposition p: If yes, then the additional knowledge won’t improve her situation with respect to knowledge of p; if not, then the additional knowledge won’t help her with respect to knowledge of p. To be sure: It might well be good to know more rather than less but this point seems irrelevant to the topic here.

  11. This view is much stronger than the (quite popular) mere denial of the necessity claim or the sufficiency claim.

  12. Sinnott-Armstrong (2004, 2006) defends contrastivism but does not want any contextualism in his theory—Similar problems arise for any combination of epistemic contrastivism with epistemic relativism (see, e.g., MacFarlane 2005 and also Kölbel 2002).

  13. Thanks to a referee for pressing me here and coming up with this idea.

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1979). Other minds. In J. O. Urmson & G. J. Warnock (Eds.), Philosophical papers (3rd ed., pp. 76–116). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baumann, P. (2008). Problems for Sinnott-Armstrong’s moral contrastivism. The Philosophical Quarterly 58, 463–470.

  • Baumann, P. (2012). Knowledge, practical reasoning and action. Logos & Episteme, 3(1), 7–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism. Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators. The Journal of Philosophy, 69, 1007–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1972). Contrastive statements. The Philosophical Review, 81, 411–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40, 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2002). Evidence, pragmatics, and justification. The Philosophical Review, 111, 67–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1992). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. In A. I. Goldman (Ed.), Liaisons. Philosophy meets the cognitive and social sciences (pp. 85–103). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, B. (2001). Contextualist swords, skeptical plowshares. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 385–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, A. (2014). Whole-hearted motivation and relevant alternatives: A problem for the contrastivist account of moral reasons. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 17, 835–845.

  • Karjalainen, A., & Morton, A. (2003). Contrastive knowledge. Philosophical Explorations, 6(2), 74–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2002). Truth without objectivity. London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 197–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Resnik, M. (1987). Choices. An introduction to decision theory. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive knowledge. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 235–271). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2004). Classy pyrrhonism. In W. Sinnott-Arnstrong (Ed.), Pyrrhonian skepticism (pp. 188–207). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006). Moral skepticisms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Snedegar, J. (2013a). Contrastive semantics for deontic modals. In M. Blaauw (Ed.), Contrastivism in philosophy (pp. 116–133). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snedegar, J. (2013b). Reasons claims and contrastivism about reasons. Philosophical Studies, 166, 231–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Baumann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baumann, P. Epistemic Contrastivism, Knowledge and Practical Reasoning. Erkenn 81, 59–68 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9728-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9728-z

Keywords

Navigation