Skip to main content
Log in

Knowledge and Approximate Knowledge

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditionally, epistemologists have held that only truth-related factors matter in the question of whether a subject can be said to know a proposition. Various philosophers have recently departed from this doctrine by claiming that the answer to this question also depends on practical concerns. They take this move to be warranted by the fact that people’s knowledge attributions appear sensitive to contextual variation, in particular variation due to differing stakes. This paper proposes an alternative explanation of the aforementioned fact, one that allows us to stick to the orthodoxy. The alternative applies the conceptual spaces approach to the concept of knowledge. With knowledge conceived of spatially, the variability in knowledge attributions follows from recent work on identity, according to which our standards for judging things (including concepts) to be identical are context-dependent. On the proposal to be made, it depends on what is at stake in a context whether it is worth distinguishing between knowing and being at least close to knowing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bayesian decision theory is sometimes criticized on the grounds that it is highly idealized. But, first, the same is true for virtually any scientific theory. Second, there is a promising ongoing de-idealization program; see in particular Weirich’s work in this vein (e.g., (2004)).

  2. See Unger (1975) and, for a more recent treatment, Davis (2007). Lewis (1979) also observes the context-dependence of standards of precision, but for him these have semantic rather than (merely) pragmatic significance. Lewis (1996) is naturally read as developing this idea into a contextualist semantics of “knows.”

  3. See also Kennedy (2007:24 f) on the relation between standards of precision and what is at stake in a context.

  4. See, e.g., Hetherington (2012), Starmans and Friedman (2012), and Turri (2012). See Nagel et al. (2013) and Starmans and Friedman (2013) for worthwhile discussion.

  5. At least this is so on all of the quantitative measures of inductive and abductive strength that one finds in the literature.

  6. See Oddie (2007) for an overview of the literature and for some examples of measures of truth-closeness. Authors concerned with vagueness have also proposed accounts in which truth admits of degrees. See, for instance, Edgington (1997) and Smith (2008).

  7. As an anonymous referee rightly reminded us, knowledge is generally taken to be factive. Whether this makes knowledge incompatible with a non-maximal degree of truth is not so clear, however. For instance, Edgington (1997) can be read as suggesting that a degree of truth close to the maximum may be enough for qualifying as true in a categorical sense. Also, Cobreros et al.’s (2012) distinction between strict and tolerant truth, where the latter is defined in terms of similarity to classical truth, may help to account for our intuition that knowledge is factive even if knowledge is compatible with a non-maximal degree of truth: knowledge may be factive in the sense that it requires tolerant truth, but no strict truth.

  8. If you believe that it is 323.992 m high, can you know that it is 323.992 m high if it is 323.9924 m high? And so on.

  9. If geometrically representing knowledge requires more than three dimensions, then the question is to be asked in terms of hypercubes, hyperplanes, etc.

  10. We have defined the utilities such that they are always positive. This choice is inconsequential: only the relative utilities matter, since they determine the differences between expected utilities of various actions (i.e., the absolute utilities are on an interval scale rather than a ratio scale).

  11. In the example in the text above, we had that x L  = 2, x H  = 20, and y = 1.

  12. It should be easy to see how this schematic situation fits both the Bank Cases and the Airport Cases. For the Bank Cases, let h 1 be the hypothesis that the bank is open on Saturday, and let \(h_2 = \neg h_1\). Furthermore, let a 1 be the option of going to the bank on Friday; a 2 the option of going to the bank on Saturday; x the utility of going to the bank while it is open; and y the utility of avoiding the long queues on Friday. For the Airport Cases, let h 1 be the hypothesis that the intended flight has a layover in Chicago, with again \(h_2 = \neg h_1\). Let a 1 be the option of contacting the airline and rescheduling the flight if necessary; a 2 the option of taking the intended flight; x the utility of having a layover in Chicago; and y the utility of avoiding the hassle of contacting the airline.

  13. Applied to the Bank Cases: if the agent is completely certain that the bank will be closed on Saturday, she will go there on Friday, which is her only option to achieve her main goal.

  14. Applied to the Bank Cases again: if the agent is completely certain that the bank will be open on Saturday, she will go there on Saturday, which allows her to achieve her main goal while avoiding the queues on Friday.

  15. As an anonymous referee observed, variants of DeRose’s Bank Cases could be used to argue for the context-sensitivity of attributions of certainty. The referee also observed that our decision-theoretic explanation of the context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions would generalize swiftly to an explanation of the context-sensitivity of certainty attributions.

  16. We are greatly indebted to René van Woudenberg and to an anonymous referee for this journal for very helpful comments on previous versions of this paper.

References

  • Bach, K. (2005). The emperor’s new ‘knows’. In G. Preyer, & G. Peter (Eds.) Contextualism in philosophy (pp. 51–89). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1993). Sensory qualities. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Égré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic 41, 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1987). Knowledge, context, and social standards. Synthese 73, 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13, 57–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. (2007). Knowledge claims and context: Loose use. Philosophical Studies 132, 395–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2013). What is graded membership?. Noûs, in press.

  • DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, 913–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the sceptical puzzle. Philosophical Review 104, 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1996), Knowledge, assertion, and lotteries. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 568–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2004). The context-insensitivity of ‘Knowing More’ and ‘Knowing Better’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34, 313–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2008a). Underdetermination. In S. Psillos, M. Curd (Eds.) The routledge companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 292–301). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2008b). Knowledge and practical reasoning. Dialectica 62, 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., Decock, L. (2010). Identity and similarity. Philosophical Studies 151, 59–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1997). Vagueness by degrees. In R. Keefe, P. Smith (Eds.) Vagueness: A Reader (pp. 294–316). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2001). Skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philosophical Studies 103, 61–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Analysis 63, 194–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces. Cambridge MA: Bradford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2007). Representing actions and functional properties in conceptual spaces. In T. Ziemke, J. Zlatev, R. M. Frank (Eds.) Body, language and mind (Vol. 1, pp. 167–195). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P, & Warglien, M. (2011). Using concept spaces to model actions and events. Journal of Semantics (In press).

  • Gärdenfors, P, & Zenker, F. (2011). Using conceptual spaces to model the dynamics of empirical theories. In: E. J., Olsson, S. Enqvist (Eds.), Belief revision meets philosophy of science (pp. 137–153). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P., Zenker, F. (2012). Theory change as dimensional change: Conceptual spaces applied to the dynamics of empirical theories. Synthese (In press).

  • Goldman, A., Olsson, E. J. (2009). Reliabilism and the value of knowledge. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.) Epistemic Value (pp. 19–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2011). On intellectualism in epistemology. Mind 120, 705–733.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazlett, A. (2010). The myth of factive verbs. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 497–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2001). Good knowledge, bad knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2012) There can be lucky knowledge. In: M. Steup, J. Turri, E. Sosa (Eds.) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Oxford: Wiley–Blackwell (In press).

  • Kennedy, C. (2007). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy 30, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2000). Contextualism and the real nature of academic skepticism. Philosophical Issues 10, 108–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2000). The contextualist evasion of epistemology. Philosophical Issues 10, 24–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krecz, C. (1986). Parts and pieces. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46, 381–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2002). Be brief and be vague. In: D. Restle, D. Zaefferer (Eds.), Sounds and systems: Studies in structure and change (pp. 439–458). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8, 339–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1981). Causal decision theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59, 5–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1962). Certainty. In: his Philosophical Papers (pp. 226–251). New York: Collier Books.

  • Nagel, J., San Juan, V., Mar, R. (2013). Lay denial of knowledge for justified true beliefs. Cognition (In press).

  • Oakley, I. T. (2001) A skeptic’s reply to Lewisian contextualism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31, 309–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2007). “Truthlikeness,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truthlikeness/.

  • Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth?. Journal of Philosophy 94, 246–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984) Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radford, C. (1966). Knowledge—by examples. Analysis 27, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs 35, 477–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartwell, C. (1992). Why knowledge is merely true belief. Journal of Philosophy 89, 167–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). Contextualist solutions to skepticism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96, 317–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (2008). Vagueness and degrees of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2000). Skepticism and contextualism. Philosophical Issues 10, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Starmans, C., Friedman, O. (2012). The folk conception of knowledge. Cognition 124, 272–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmans, C., Friedman, O. (2013). Taking ‘know’ for an answer: A reply to Nagel, San Juan, and Mar. Cognition (In press).

  • Turri, J. (2012). Is knowledge justified true belief?. Synthese 184, 247–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance: A case for scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Deemter, K. (2010). Not exactly. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weirich, P. (2004). Realistic decision theory: Rules for nonideal agents in nonideal circumstances. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1980). Sameness and substance. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Igor Douven.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Decock, L., Douven, I., Kelp, C. et al. Knowledge and Approximate Knowledge. Erkenn 79 (Suppl 6), 1129–1150 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9544-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9544-2

Keywords

Navigation