Skip to main content
Log in

The Best Humean System for Statistical Mechanics

  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Classical statistical mechanics posits probabilities for various events to occur, and these probabilities seem to be objective chances. This does not seem to sit well with the fact that the theory’s time evolution is deterministic. We argue that the tension between the two is only apparent. We present a theory of Humean objective chance and show that chances thus understood are compatible with underlying determinism and provide an interpretation of the probabilities we find in Boltzmannian statistical mechanics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The presentation of HOC in this section is based on Frigg and Hoefer (2010). The classical source is (Lewis 1980). But as we will see below, our version of HOC differs from Lewis’ in important respects.

  2. As is well known, there are different axiomatisations of probability. Nothing in what follows depends on which axiomatisation we chose.

  3. We use this term in restrictive way: only statements having exactly that form are chance rules. Existence claims, statements about upper and lower bounds, or specifications of probability intervals are not chance rules in our sense.

  4. This point has been made by Hájek (2007) for propensities. His arguments readily carry over to any notion of chance.

  5. In this we disagree with Lewis, who thought it a major problem to prove that chances satisfy the axioms of probability. THOC defines chance, and a function that does not satisfy the axioms of probability cannot be a chance function.

  6. Justifying PP is a thorny issue, and, unsurprisingly, one fraught with controversy. We refer the reader to Frigg and Hoefer (2010, Section 3.4) and references therein for a discussion.

  7. For a discussion see Hoefer (2007, 553–555 and 558–560). Some philosophers maintain that the PP needs no admissibility clause. For counter-arguments in favour of the necessity of an admissibility clause in PP see (Hoefer 2014).

  8. Note that even if you believe that the world does contain necessary connections, powers or propensities, it still also has a HM. The HM is just the panoply of actual events understood as purely occurrent, setting aside any modal aspects those events may possess. The Humean about chance then simply maintains that chance facts supervene on this HM.

  9. For a discussion of infinite sequences see (Elga 2004).

  10. The assumption that macrostates can be indexed by an integer k is a common idealisation in this context and we follow this convention here; see (Frigg 2008b) and references therein.

  11. This definition of TD-likeness is adapted from Lavis (2005). A different way of reformulating the Second Law emerges from (Albert 2000). We prefer an approach based on TD-likeness for the reasons outlined in (Frigg and Werndl 2011) and use it here because it is simpler than Albert’s. Noting we say about chance depends on this choice, though, and mutatis mutandis our account of chance can also be applied to Albert’s transition probabilities.

  12. We base our discussion on the standard possible worlds definition of determinism; see (Earman 1986, Ch. 2).

  13. We restrict attention to Boltzmannian SM. For detailed discussions of that theory, as well as of the Gibbsian approach which we set aside here, see Frigg (2008b) and Uffink (2006).

  14. Note that the term ‘Past Hypothesis’ is usually reserved for approaches in which the system under consideration is the entire universe; it then says that the universe came into being in a low entropy macrostate provided to us by modern Big Bang cosmology. We return to the issue of the nature of systems studied in SM Sect. 5.5.

  15. For an accessible introduction see (Berkovitz et al. 2011). We assume that the relevant systems are ergodic (Frigg and Werndl 2011).

  16. Note that determining what will happen is not the same as entailing that the objective chance of something happening is equal to one (and mutatis mutandis for not happening and chance equal to zero).

  17. Note that on our understanding of admissibility, it is not closed under logical conjunction, as Lewis supposed it to be.

  18. While Lewis tried to suppress this element of pragmatism and user-relativity as much as he could without actually saying much at all about simplicity and strength, other BSA advocates such as Albert (2011), Callender and Cohen (2009) and Schrenk (2008) have openly embraced it.

  19. That said, we are sympathetic with Lewis’ line on this point (1994, 479): we may, not unreasonably in light of actual science, hope that there is one robustly Best System for our HM, or a small family of closely resembling cousins, that come out as Best under any reasonable ways of cashing out and weighing up the qualities of simplicity, strength and fit.

  20. Roughly, the Kolmogorov complexity is the length of the shortest computer programme that derives a certain result. With respect to a given language, the Kolmogorov complexity is an objective quantity.

  21. In a phenomenon known as ‘gene surfing’, genetic drift becomes a much stronger evolutionary force in populations at the edge of a territorial expansion wave, because genes from the individuals at/near the edge of the wave will be disproportionately represented in the gene pool of the newly colonized regions in subsequent generations. Lehe et al. (2012) propose (in our terms) chance rules for the fixation of a favorable mutation as a function of distance of the individual in which the mutation occurs from the edge of the colonization wave.

  22. For a discussion of this point see (Frisch 2011, forthcoming).

  23. This is so even if the output of the rule is merely a chance rather than a yes/no determination. When it comes to the chance \( p(TS) \), which is almost always near-1, the information conveyed to the agent is nearly as strong as what is entailed by (but impossible to derive from) the deterministic laws plus IC’s.

  24. In this section our discussion idealises by pretending that the histories of all sorts of different SM systems could be treated as representable via paths in a single phase space. This is an idealisation because systems with a different particle number N have different phase spaces. We think that this is no threat to our approach. SM systems such as expanding gases and cooling solids are ubiquitous in HM and there will be enough of them for most N to ground a HBS supervenience claim. Those for which this is not the case (probably ones with very large N) can be treated along the lines of rare gambling devices such as dodecahedra: they will be seen as falling into the same class as more common systems and a flat distribution over possible initial conditions will be the best distribution in much the same way in which the 1/n rule is the best for all gambling devices.

  25. In Sect. 4 we argued that if allowed to compete, some higher-level rules or laws may well deserve to make it into the Best System. Here the question is the prior one, which Lewis answered negatively: should such rules even be allowed to compete?

  26. Fodor famously used multiple realisability as an argument against reduction (1974). Following (Dizadji-Bahmani et al. 2010) we think that this is going too far, but multiple realisability does provide an argument against eliminativism.

  27. Lyon (2011) and Glynn (2010, 25–26) argue convincingly that CTC is unacceptable in any case no matter what view of chance one adopts.

  28. In Schaffer’s notation, ch < p e′ , w, t > is the chance in world w, assessed at time t, that the proposition p e (asserting that event e happens) is true.

References

  • Albert, D. (2000). Time and chance. Cambridge/MA and London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, D. (2011). Physics and chance. In Y. Ben-Menahem & M. Hemmo (Eds.), Probability in physics (pp. 17–40). Berlin: Springer.

  • Anderson, P. W. (1972). More is different. Science, New Series, 177, 393–396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J., Frigg, R., & Kronz, F. (2011). The ergodic hierarchy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Summer 2011 Edition: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/ergodic-hierarchy/.

  • Callender, C., & Cohen, J. (2009). A better best system account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain. Cambridge/MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dizadji-Bahmani, F., Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Who’s afraid of Nagelian reduction? Erkenntnis, 73, 393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2006). The constituents of life. http://www.umb.no/statisk/causci/SpinozalecturesDupre.pdf.

  • Earman, J. (1986). A primer on determinsim. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2004). Infinitesimal chances and the laws of nature. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences and the disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese, 28, 77–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2008a). Chance in Boltzmannian statistical mechanics. Philosophy of Science, 75, 670–681.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2008b). A field guide to recent work on the foundations of statistical mechanics. In D. Rickles (Ed.), The Ashgate companion to contemporary philosophy of physics (pp. 99–196). London: Ashgate.

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Probability in Boltzmannian statistical mechanics. In G. Ernst & A. Hüttemann (Eds.), Time, chance and reduction. Philosophical aspects of statistical mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Frigg, R., & Hoefer, C. (2010). Determinism and chance from a Humean perspective. In D. Dieks, W. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, M. Weber, F. Stadler & T. Uebel (Eds.), The present situation in the philosophy of science (pp. 351–372). Berlin, New York: Springer.

  • Frigg, R., & Werndl, C. (2011). Explaining thermodynamic-like behaviour In terms of epsilon-ergodicity. Philosophy of Science (Forthcoming).

  • Frisch, M. (2011). From Boltzmann to Arbuthnot: Higher-level laws and the best system. Philosophy of Science, 78, 1001–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (forthcoming). Physical fundamentalism in a Lewisian best system. In A. Wilson (Ed.), Asymmetries of chance and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Glynn, L. (2010). Deterministic chance. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 51–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2007). The reference class problem is your problem too. Synthese, 156, 563–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (2007). The third way on objctive probability: A sceptic’s guide to objective chance. Mind, 116, 549–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. (2014). Consistency and admissibility. In T. Handfield & A. Wilson (Ed.), Chance and temporal asymmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press (Forthcoming).

  • Horgan, T., & Woodward, J. (1985). Folk psychology is here to stay. Philosophical Review, 94, 197–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). The mind-body problem after fifty years. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Current issues in philosophy of mind (pp. 3–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lavis, D. (2005). Boltzmann and Gibbs: An attempted reconciliation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 36, 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehe, R., Hallatschek, O., & Peliti, L. (2012). The rate of beneficial mutations surfing on the wave of a range expansion. PLoS Computatinal Biology, 8, e1002447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In R. C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. 2, pp. 83–132). Berkeley: University of California Press (reprinted in Lewis 1986, with postscripts added).

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1999). Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2001). Determinism and chance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32, 609–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2004). David Lewis’ Humean theory of objective chance. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1115–1125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A. (2011). Deterministic probability: Neither chance nor credence. Synthese, 182, 413–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redhead, M. (1995). From physics to metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2007). Deterministic chance? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 113–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. (2008). A theory for special sciences laws. In H. Bohse, K. Dreimann & S. Walter (Eds.), Selected papers contributed to the sections of GAP.6, 6th international congress of the society for analytical philosophy. Paderborn: Mentis.

  • Uffink, J. (2006). Compendium of the foundations of classical statistical physics. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Philosophy of physics (pp. 923–1047). Amsterdam: North Holland.

  • van Inwagen, P. (1994). Composition as identity. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 207–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1993). Dreams of a final theory: The search for the fundamental laws of nature. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was presented at the IHPST workshop “Probability in Biology and Physics” in Paris, February 2009. We would like to thank the organisers for the opportunity and the audience for stimulating comments. Furthermore, We would like to thank Nancy Cartwright, José Díez, Jossi Berkovitz, Mathias Frisch, Barry Loewer, Alan Hájek, Aidan Lyon, Kristina Musholt, Huw Price, Josefa Toribio, and Eric Winsberg for helpful discussions. Thanks are also due to two anonymous referees for helpful comments. RF acknowledges financial support from Grant FFI2012-37354 of the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation (MICINN). CH acknowledges the generous support of Spanish MICINN grants FFI2008-06418-C03-03 and FFI2011-29834-C03-03, AGAUR grant SGR2009-01528, and MICINN Consolider-Ingenio grant CSD2009-00056.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roman Frigg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Frigg, R., Hoefer, C. The Best Humean System for Statistical Mechanics. Erkenn 80 (Suppl 3), 551–574 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9541-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9541-5

Keywords

Navigation