Skip to main content
Log in

Emergence, Closure and Inter-level Causation in Biological Systems

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we advocate the idea that an adequate explanation of biological systems requires appealing to organizational closure as an emergent causal regime. We first develop a theoretical justification of emergence in terms of relatedness, by arguing that configurations, because of the relatedness among their constituents, possess ontologically irreducible properties, providing them with distinctive causal powers. We then focus on those emergent causal powers exerted as constraints, and we claim that biological systems crucially differ from other natural systems in that they realize a closure of constraints, i.e. a second-order emergent regime of causation such that the constituents, each of them acting as a constraint, realize a mutual dependence among them, and are collectively able to self-maintain. Lastly, we claim that closure can be justifiably taken as an emergent regime of causation, without admitting that it inherently involves whole-parts causation, which would require to commit to stronger ontological and epistemological assumptions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Weber and Varela (2002) for a discussion of the Kantian rooting of this scientific tradition.

  2. It is worth noting that this meaning of ‘closure’ has nothing to do with Kim’s one, which is at work in his argument about the “causal closure of the physical domain”. According to the latter, as Kim explains, “any physical event that has a cause at time t has a physical cause at t. This is the assumption that if we trace the causal ancestry of a physical event, we need never go outside the physical domain”(Kim 1993: 280).

  3. We take here the notion of “inclusivity of levels” as analogous to Kim’s “Causal Inheritance Principle” (Kim 1993, p. 326), according to which if a property M is realized when its physical realization bases P is instantiated, the causal powers of M are identical with the causal powers of P. By the choice of “inclusivity of levels” we want to emphasize the idea that in the natural world all causes are physical or are the result of the interaction between physical entities: no special causes (vitalist, spiritual, etc., that are not physically instantiated) are introduced at different levels, e.g. at the biological and the mental ones. It should be noted that Kim’s argument also requires the Causal Closure Principle as a premise, in the sense that the ultimate reduction of an emergent property to its fundamental realization base is possible only if the basal level is causally closed (Kim 2003). Yet, we maintain that the validity of the inclusivity of levels does not necessarily require appealing to causal closure: emergent causal powers can be reduced to basal powers even though the latter are not shown or supposed to be closed. Consequently, the argument we develop in this paper does not depend on the Causal Closure Principle.

  4. For Kim's purposes, the exclusion argument is originally targeted at mental causation and is not supposed to imply causal drainage. As a matter of fact, Kim himself has vehemently tried to avoid causal drain drainage as the ultimate consequence of the argument of this argument in favour of reduction. In addition, on the basis of a commitment to the Standard Model and its bottom level of fundamental physical particles, he rejects the arguments based on the possibility of the absence of a rock-bottom level of reality. For a detailed discussion of these issues see, for example Block’s criticism of Kim’s reduction argument (Block 2003) and Kim’s reply (Kim 2003).

  5. The idea of a basic level with self-sufficient basic entities has been deeply questioned in microphysics, the very domain reductionist approaches appeal to as fundamental, where relational and heuristic accounts have taken place (Bitbol 2007).

  6. The distinction has however been formulated, for instance by Silberstein and McGeever (1999), according to which epistemological emergence concerns models or formalisms, while ontological emergence involves irreducible causal capacities. Here, we follow this conventional distinction.

  7. Van Gulick (2001) refers to resultant and emergent properties as “specific value emergent” and “modest kind emergent” properties, respectively.

  8. Crutchfield, for instance, distinguished two different definitions and classes of models of emergence according to two different limitations in our capability “in principle” to describe emergent phenomena: nonpredictability and nondeducibility (Crutchfield 1994).

  9. The debate between a relational and an atomistic interpretation of the supervenience and emergence base has a long history that dates back to the first formulations of the notion of emergence in the British Emergentism. In Alexander’s framework, for example, space and time, the lower level on which the whole natural world emerge, are relational concepts, not definable separately (Alexander 1920). The opposition between atomistic and relational approaches is particularly evident in Lloyd Morgan’s work. In contrast to the billiard balls model of extrinsic interactions, he presents the idea of relatedness based on inherent relations, that contributes to specify the properties of the terms involved in the relation (Lloyd Morgan 1923, p. 19). It is also worth noting that according to some authors, Kim’s reference to relations is still made in a fundamentally atomistic framework, and does not imply a clear commitment to relational mereological supervenience, which implies the idea that relations “do not simply influence the parts, but supersede or subsume their independent existence in an irreducibly relational structure” (Thompson 2007, p. 428).

  10. The interpretation of relational mereological supervenience in terms of constitution is consistent, we argue, with the position developed by Craver and Bechtel (2007) within their mechanistic framework. As they suggest, the relations between constituents located at different levels in a mechanism are better understood as constitutive relations (pp. 554–555). See Sect. 7 below for a detailed discussion.

  11. For simplicity, we will only refer, from now on, to ‘configurational properties S 1 , …, S n ’ (equivalent to ‘property M’), and to ‘whole W’ (equivalent to ‘supervenience base B’).

  12. It is important to emphasise that configurational properties must be actually realised, and not just “dispositional”. As a consequence, a configuration C is functionally irreducible, in this account, also to those entities that would possess the “potential disposition” to actualise these properties.

  13. It is worth noting that the relation between the emergent properties and its emergence base can be interpreted both synchronically and diachronically. Being based on novelty, in fact, the irreducibility to any entity that does not belong to an actual configuration is in principle compatible with both the dimensions of emergence. See also footnote 21 below.

  14. The concept of closure has been proposed by several influential authors, that we have mentioned in the introduction. For a recent survey, see Chandler & Van De Vijver (2000). Mossio (2013) provides a synthetic overview of the meaning and uses of the term in the biological domain.

  15. Or, at least, systems being ‘at the edge’ of the biological domain. We do not discuss this issue here, since it does not interfere with the central point.

  16. It is of course conceivable that a description of constraints might possibly be given in terms of thermodynamics, specifically as entities not being affected by the thermodynamic flow. However, in this case, constraints (and then closure) would not be reduced to a different causal regime, but simply redescribed in different terms.

  17. This allows distinguishing, moreover, a closure of constraints from a cycle of processes or reactions as, for instance, the water cycle. In the case of cycles, the entities and processes involved in the cycle (e.g. clouds, rain, spring, river, sea, clouds …) do not act as constraints on each other, and the system can be adequately described by appealing to a set of external boundary conditions (ground, sun …) acting on a single causal regime of thermodynamic changes (see also Mossio and Moreno 2010).

  18. In this framework, functions are interpreted in an organizational sense: a trait is functional if and only if it exerts a constraint that is subject to closure and, consequently, contributes to the maintenance of the organization while being maintained by that very organization. As extensively discussed in Mossio et al. (2009) the organizational account of functions integrates in a unified framework both etiological and causal-systemic theories of function.

  19. According to Lloyd Morgan, “[…] when some new kind of relatedness is supervenient (say at the level of life), the way in which the physical events which are involved run their course is different in virtue of its presence-different from what it would have been if life had been absent. […]. I shall say that this new manner in which lower events happen—this touch of novelty in evolutionary advance depends on the new kind of relatedness” (Lloyd Morgan 1923, p. 16). According to Stephan (1992) Lloyd Morgan’s passage could admit different interpretations, such as that of a logical claim about supervenience. On the contrary, McLaughlin asserts: “In Morgan one finds the notion of downward causation clearly and forcefully articulated” (McLaughlin 1992, p. 68).

  20. Campbell defines downward causation as follows: “all processes at the lower level of a hierarchy are restrained by and act in conformity to the laws of the higher level” (1974, p. 180).

  21. In the philosophical literature, nested causation comes in two variants, synchronic and diachronic (Kim 2010, pp. 34–36). On the one hand, synchronic nested causation refers to the situation in which upward and downward causation would occur simultaneously. In more technical terms, a supervenient property M acts causally on its supervenience base S 1 , …, S n at the same time that the supervenience base generates M. On the other hand, diachronic (or diagonal) nested causation refers to the situation in which M acts on its own supervenience base S 1 , …, S n , causing its modification, but only at a subsequent time with respect to the upward determination. In this paper, however, we assume that the distinction is irrelevant, since we question the very idea of the causal influence of M on S 1 , …, S n , be it synchronic or diachronic.

  22. A satisfactory analysis of downward causation, then, requires a careful distinction between two ideas. One is the idea that a configuration is made up by a set of constituents, which have causal interactions between them. Explaining why a given molecule of water is rotating in a given manner at a given moment requires an appeal to its causal interactions with other constituents. And the reason why a set of constituents may exert a causal influence on other constituents is, of course, that all of them belong to the same system. The other idea, in contrast, is that the ‘whole system’, including any specific constituent, would have a causal role on that very constituent.

  23. The physical processes on which the network exerts (constraining) causal powers can, in some cases, become members of the network itself, when they enter into configurations which act as constraints. Nonetheless, the network would exert causal powers on them as long as they are part of its surroundings, and it would cease acting causally on them as soon as they would start playing the role of constraints.

  24. In the case of the wheel, for instance, one may say that if we describe a given molecule as a constituent of a wheel, we are already including in the description all constitutive and relational properties, which make it a constituent (‘being in such and such position’, ‘having such and such interactions and links with neighbouring molecules’ …), and which determine its behaviour under specific conditions. For instance, a force (i.e. gravity) applied to a part will generate a chain of causal interactions among the constituents which, because of their individual configurational properties, will behave in a specific way. We will then call the collective pattern the ‘rolling movement of the wheel’. Each molecule of the wheel will move in a specific way because its configurational properties force it to do so, and a complete description of the configurational properties of the individual constituent will suffice to explain why it behaves as it does. The fact that the constituents collectively constitute a wheel, whose macroscopic behaviour can be described as a rolling movement, does not add anything to the explanation of the individual behaviour. There are indeed causal interactions here, but not inter-level causation.

  25. See Bich (2012) for an epistemological discussion of the relationship between emergence and downward causation.

  26. It should be noted, however, that the issue is currently being explored by several biologists and theoreticians. For instance, a relevant proposal in this direction has recently been developed by Soto, Sonnenschein and Miquel (Soto et al. 2008).

References

  • Alexander, S. (1920). Space, time and deity. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L. (2012). Complex emergence and the living organization: An epistemological framework for biology. Synthese, 185, 215–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M. (2007). Ontology, matter and emergence. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Science, 6, 293–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2003). Do causal powers drain away? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(1), 133–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1974). Downward causation in hierarchically organized biological systems. In F. J. Ayala & T. Dobzhansky (Eds.), Studies in the philosophy of biology (pp. 179–186). Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. J., & Bickhard, M. H. (2011). Physicalism, emergence and downward causation. Axiomathes, 21(1), 33–56. Quotations from the online version: http://www.lehigh.edu/~mhb0/physicalemergence.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, J. L. R., & Van De Vijver, G. (Eds.). (2000). Closure: Emergent organizations and their dynamics (Vol. 901). New York: Annals of the New York Academy of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandrasekhar, S. (1961). Hydrodynamic and hydromagnetic stability. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornish-Bowden, A., Cárdenas, M. L., Letelier, J.-C., & Soto Andrade, J. (2007). Beyond reductionism: Metabolic circularity as a guiding vision for a real biology of systems. Proteomics, 7, 839–845.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 547–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crutchfield, J. P. (1994). The calculi of emergence: Computations, dynamics, and induction. Physica D: Nonlinear Phenomena, 75, 11–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C., Køppe, S., & Stjernfelt, F. (2000). Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. In P. B. Andersen, C. Emmeche, N. O. Finnemann, & P. V. Christensen (Eds.), Downward causation (pp. 13–34). Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fell, D. (1997). Understanding the control of metabolism. London: Portland University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (1975). Organization of chemical reactions into dividing and metabolizing units: The chemotons. BioSystems, 7, 15–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganti, T. (2003). The principles of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glansdorff, P., & Prigogine, I. (1971). Thermodynamics of structure, stability and fluctuations. London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmeyr, H.-J. S. (2007). The biochemical factory that autonomously fabricates itself: A systems biological view of the living cell. In F. Boogerd, F. J. Bruggerman, J.-H. S. Hofmeyr, & H. V. Westerhoff (Eds.), Systems biology: Philosophical foundations (pp. 217–242). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. (2009). Top-down causation and autonomy in complex systems. In N. Murphy, G. Ellis, & T. O’Connor (Eds.), Downward causation and the neurobiology of free will (pp. 83–102). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, E. [1781] (1987). Kritik der Urteilskraft (Critique of Judgment). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Kauffman, S. (2000). Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1993). Supervenience and mind: Selected philosophical essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1997). Explanation, prediction and reduction in emergentism. Intellectica, 25(2), 45–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2003). Blocking causal drainage and other maintenance chores with mental causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(1), 151–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2006). Emergence: Core Ideas and Issues. Synthese, 151(3), 547–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2010). Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laughlin, R., & Pines, D. (2000). The theory of everything. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the United States of America, 97, 28–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laughlin, R., Pines, D., Schmalien, J., Stojkovic, B., & Wolynes, P. (2000). The middle way. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the United States of America, 97, 32–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd Morgan, C. (1923). Emergent evolution. London: Williams and Norgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luisi, P.-L. (2006). The emergence of life: From chemical origins to synthetic biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition. The realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (2004). What makes biology unique? Considerations on the autonomy of a scientific discipline. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. P. (1992). The rise and fall of British emergentism. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism (pp. 49–93). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic. London: Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M. (2013). Closure. In W. Dubitzky, O. Wolkenhauer, K.-H. Cho & H. Yokota (Eds.), Encyclopedia of systems biology. New York: Springer.

  • Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2010). Organizational closure in biological organisms. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 32(2–3), 269–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 813–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolis, G., & Prigogine, I. (1977). Self-organization in nonequilibrium systems: From dissipative structures to order through fluctuations. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (1972). Laws, constraints, symbols and languages. In C. H. Waddington (Ed.), Towards a theoretical biology 4: Essays (pp. 248–258). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (Ed.) (1973). Hierarchy theory. The challenge of complex systems. New York: Georges Braziller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie et Connaissance. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1972). Some relational cell models: The metabolism-repair systems. In R. Rosen (Ed.), Foundations of mathematical biology (Vol. II, pp. 217–253). New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1991). Life itself: A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2001). Physical conditions for the appearance of autonomous systems with open-ended evolutionary capacities. PhD Dissertation, University of the Basque Country.

  • Saborido, C., Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2011). Biological organization and cross-generation functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 583–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M., & McGeever, J. (1999). The search for ontological emergence. Philosophical Quarterly, 50(195), 182–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soto, A. M., Sonnenschein, C., & Miquel, P. A. (2008). On physicalism and downward causation in developmental and cancer biology. Acta Biotheoretica, 56, 257–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperry, R. W. (1969). A modified concept of consciousness. Psychological Review, 76(6), 532–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephan, A. (1992). Emergence—A systematic view on its historical facets. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism (pp. 25–48). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (1986). Relational holism and quantum mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37, 71–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Umerez, J., & Mossio, M. (2013). Constraint. In W. Dubitzky, O. Wolkenhauer, K.-H. Cho & H. Yokota (Eds.), Encyclopedia of systems biology. New York: Springer.

  • Van Gulick, R. (2001). Reduction, emergence and other recent options on the mind/body problem: A philosophical overview. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(9–10), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Maturana, H., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. BioSystems, 5, 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vicente, A. (2011). Current physics and ‘the physical’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(2), 393–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors wish to thank Jon Umerez and Agustin Vicente for very valuable feedback on earlier versions of this paper. This work was funded by Ministerio de Ciencia y Innovación, Spain (‘Juan de la Cierva’ program to LB); Research Projects of the Spanish Government (FFU2009-12895-CO2-02 to AM and FFI2011-25665 to AM and LB); Research Projects of the Basque Government (IT 505-10 and IT 590-13 to AM and LB).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leonardo Bich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mossio, M., Bich, L. & Moreno, A. Emergence, Closure and Inter-level Causation in Biological Systems. Erkenn 78 (Suppl 2), 153–178 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9507-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9507-7

Keywords

Navigation