Skip to main content
Log in

The Knowledge Argument and Epiphenomenalism

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Frank Jackson endorses epiphenomenalism because he thinks that his knowledge argument undermines physicalism. One of the most interesting criticisms of Jackson’s position is what I call the ‘inconsistency objection’. The inconsistency objection says that Jackson’s position is untenable because epiphenomenalism undermines the knowledge argument. The inconsistency objection has been defended by various philosophers independently, including Michael Watkins, Fredrik Stjernberg, and Neil Campbell. Surprisingly enough, while Jackson himself admits explicitly that the inconsistency objection is ‘the most powerful reply to the knowledge argument’ he knows of, it has never been discussed critically. The aim of this paper is to evaluate the objection and to identify and consider its implications. The objection is alleged to be based on a causal theory of knowledge. I argue that the objection fails by showing that any causal theory of knowledge is such that it is either false or does not support the inconsistency objection. In order to defend my argument, I offer a hypothesis concerning phenomenal knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For overviews of the debate on the knowledge argument, see Alter (1999, 2007), Stoljar and Nagasawa (2004) and Nagasawa (2009).

  2. After 16 years of defending the knowledge argument, Jackson announced in 1998 that he had changed his mind, stating that although the argument contained no obvious fallacy, its conclusion, that physicalism is false, must be mistaken. In this paper, I am concerned only with Jackson’s original antiphysicalist position. See Jackson (1995, 1998, 2003, 2004).

  3. Strictly speaking, the inconsistency objection is not a response to the knowledge argument per se, but to the joint holding of cogency of the knowledge argument and epiphenomenalism. Jackson calls the inconsistency objection the ‘“there must be a reply” reply’ because he thinks that the objection shows that there must be a successful physicalist reply to the knowledge argument without specifying exactly what the reply is. See Sect. 4 for Jackson’s construal of the inconsistency objection.

  4. See Jackson (1982) for his endorsement of type epiphenomenalism.

  5. Thanks to Alter for drawing my attention to this passage.

  6. In this paper, I focus only on a necessary condition for acquiring knowledge according to a causal theory of knowledge, so that my argument can be applied to as many theories of knowledge as possible.

  7. Skyrms’s objection to the revised theory is particularly strong. See Skyrms (1967).

  8. In order to avoid complications and to emphasise the structural similarity between the Sally and the Mary scenarios I omit some relevant physical and mental events in both Figs. 1 and 2. (To take one example, strictly speaking, there should be intermediate brain states between (φ) and Bm(ψ).) I can omit them legitimately because the revised causal theory says that as long as Bm(ψ) and (ψ) have a common cause they are causally connected. For the complete, and more complex, schema for the Sally scenario see Goldman (1967), p. 365.

  9. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this point.

  10. Some proponents of the inconsistency objection might think that (C3) should cover not only phenomenal knowledge, but also other kinds of knowledge. All that is required, they might claim, is to exclude knowledge about the future from the scope of (C3). I set this point aside because what I say in the main text is applicable to any thesis that holds at least (C3).

  11. See, for instance, Chalmers (2004), Nida-Rümelin (1995, 1998), and Tye (2000).

  12. See, for example, Paxon (1974), Sharpe (1975), and Skyrms (1967).

  13. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising these four counterexamples.

  14. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this point. For criticisms of the objection that appeals to the distinction between knowledge by description and knowledge by acquaintance see Alter (1998) and Stoljar and Nagasawa (2004).

  15. Jackson (1982, p. 133).

References

  • Alter, T. (1998). A limited’ defence of the knowledge argument. Philosophical Studies, 90, 35–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T. (1999). Knowledge argument, A field guide to the philosophy of mind, eds., M. Nani and M. Marraffa, http://www.uniroma3.it/kant/index.html.

  • Alter, T. (2007). Knowledge argument. In V. Max & S. Susan (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 396–405). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1990). Acquaintance with Qualia. Theoria, 61, 129–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (1996). Philosophy of mind and cognition. Blackwell: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N. (2003). An inconsistency in the knowledge argument. Erkenntnis, 58, 261–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). Conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2003). The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 220–272). Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, J. D. (2004). Phenomenal concepts and the knowledge argument. In P. Ludlow, Y. Nagasawa, & D. Stoljar (Eds.), There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument (pp. 269–298). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1985). Reduction, Qualia and the direct introspection of brain states. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 8–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). Knowing Qualia: A reply to Jackson’, in his a neurocomputational perspective (pp. 67–76). MA, MIT Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E. (1994). Phenomenal knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 136–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foss, J. (1989). On the logic of what it is like be a conscious subject. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 67, 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1967). A causal theory of knowing. Journal of Philosophy, 64, 355–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hossack, K. (2002). Self-knowledge and consciousness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 102, 163–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philosophical Quaterly, 32, 127–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1995). Postscript. In K. P. Moser & J. D. Trout (Eds.), Contemporary materialism (pp. 184–189). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). Postscript on Qualia, in his mind, method and conditionals (pp. 76–79). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2003). Mind and illusion. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Minds, persons: Royal institute of philosophy supplement 53 (pp. 251–271). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2004). Looking back on the knowledge argument. In P. Ludlow, Y. Nagasawa, & D. Stoljar (Eds.), There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness, Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument (pp. 15–19). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). What experience teaches, In Proceedings of Russellian Society (University of Sydney).

  • Loar, B. (1990). Phenomenal states. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives IV: Action theory, the philosophy of mind (pp. 109–130). Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (1997). Phenomenal states (revised version). In N. Block, O. Flanagan, & G. Güzeldere (Eds.), The nature of consciousness (pp. 597–616). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. B. (1989). Type dualism, type epiphenomenalism, and the causal priority of the physical. Philosophical Perspective, 3, 109–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin Brian, P. (1993). On Davidson’s response to the challenge of epiphenomenalism. In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.), Mental causation (pp. 27–40). Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2008). God and phenomenal consciousness: A novel approach to knowledge arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2009). The knowledge argument. In T. Bayne, A. Cleeremans, & P. Wilken (Eds.), The Oxford companion to consciousness (pp. 395–397). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemirow, L. (1990). Physicalism and the cognitive role of acquaintance. In W. G. Lycan (Ed.), Mind, cognition: A reader (pp. 490–499). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nida-Rümelin, M. (1995). What Mary couldn’t know: Belief about phenomenal states. In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Conscious experience (pp. 219–224). Imprint Academic: Exeter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nida-Rümelin, M. (1998). On belief about experiences: An epistemological distinction applied to the knowledge argument against physicalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 51–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paxon, Jr., & Thomas, D. (1974). Prof Swain’s account of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 25, 57–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharpe, R. A. (1975). On the causal theory of knowledge. Ratio, 17, 206–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1967). The explication of ‘X knows that p’. Journal of Philosophy, 64, 373–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernberg, F. (1999). Not so epiphenomenal Qualia or, how much of a mystery is the mind?’(http://www.lucs.lu.se/spinning/categories/language/Stjernberg/index.html).

  • Stoljar, D. (2001). Two conception of the physical. Philosophical and Phenomenological Research, 62, 253–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D., & Nagasawa, Y. (2004). Introduction, in their there’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, M. (1989). The knowledge argument against the knowledge argument. Analysis, 49, 158–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I presented earlier versions of this paper at the Australian National University, the Open University, the University of Birmingham, the University of Ljubljana, the University of Rijeka, the University of Kyoto and the 2006 Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association at the University of Southampton. I would like to thank all in the audience for enjoyable discussions. I am particularly grateful to Torin Alter, David Chalmers, Daniel Stoljar and anonymous referees for constructive comments and useful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yujin Nagasawa.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nagasawa, Y. The Knowledge Argument and Epiphenomenalism. Erkenn 72, 37–56 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-009-9192-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-009-9192-8

Keywords

Navigation