Skip to main content
Log in

On the Allocation of Multiple Divisible Assets to Players with Different Utilities

  • Published:
Computational Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When there is a dispute between players on how to divide multiple divisible assets, how should it be resolved? In this paper we introduce a multi-asset game model that enables cooperation between multiple agents who bargain on sharing K assets, when each player has a different value for each asset. It thus extends the sequential discrete Raiffa solution and the Talmud rule solution to multi-asset cases.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mishna Baba Metzia 2a: The first man claimed half of it belongs to him and the other claimed it all; the decision was that the one who claimed half is awarded 1 / 4 and the other is awarded 3 / 4. The principle is clear: the first man agrees that half of the garment does not belong to him. Therefore, the bargaining is only on half of the garment.

  2. Kethubot 93a: a man married three women. The first woman had a marriage contract of 100, the second of 200, and the third of 300. The man dies and his estate is worth E. The ruling of Rabbi Nathan was as follows: If the estate is worth \(E=100\), then the estate will divided equally, namely \(33\frac{1}{3}\) for each. If the estate is worth 200 the division will be (50, 75, 75) and if it is worth \(E=300\) the division is (50, 100, 150), respectively.

  3. The rules in the TAL-family (Moreno-Ternero and Villar 2006) extends the Talumd rule by using a parameter of \(\theta \in \left[ 0,1\right] \); i.e., nobody gets more than a fraction \(\theta \) of his claim if the asset value to divide is less than \(\theta \) times of the aggregate claim, and nobody gets less than a fraction \(\theta \) of his claim if the asset value to divide is larger than \(\theta \) times the aggregate claim. The extension of the Talmud rule to the multi-asset bargaining problem can be easily extended to the TAL-family rules.

  4. In our case K(N − 1) coefficients of matrix A are zeros or ones; thus, the value of L is bounded by \(O( K^2N)\), since \( L =\sum _{i,j} \log _2(a_{i,j}+1)+\log _2(nm)+(nm+m)=O( K^2N)\).

References

  • Anbarci, N., & Sun, Cj. (2013). Robustness of intermediate agreements and bargaining solutions. Games and Economic Behavior, 77(1), 367–376. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2012.11.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R. J., & Maschler, M. (1985). Game theoretic analysis of a bankruptcy problem from the talmud. Journal of Economic Theory, 36(2), 195–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, S., & Vandenberghe, L. (2004). Convex optimization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Calleja, P., Borm, P., & Hendrickx, R. (2005). Multi-issue allocation situations. European Journal of Operational Research, 164(3), 730–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagan, N., & Volij, O. (1993). The bankruptcy problem: A cooperative bargaining approach. Mathematical Social Sciences, 26(3), 287–297. doi:10.1016/0165-4896(93)90024-D.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diskin, A., Koppel, M., & Samet, D. (2011). Generalized Raiffa solutions. Games and Economic Behavior, 73(2), 452–458. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2011.04.002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • González-Alcón, C., Borm, P., & Hendrickx, R. (2007). A composite run-to-the-bank rule for multi-issue allocation situations. Mathematical Methods of Operations Research, 65(2), 339–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haake, C. J. (2009). Dividing by demanding: Object division through market procedures. International Game Theory Review, 11(01), 15–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinojosa, M., Mármol, A. M., & Sánchez, F. (2012). A consistent talmudic rule for division problems with multiple references. Top, 20(3), 661–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ju, B. G., Miyagawa, E., & Sakai, T. (2007). Non-manipulable division rules in claim problems and generalizations. Journal of Economic Theory, 132(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalai, E. (1977). Nonsymmetric Nash solutions and replications of 2-person bargaining. International Journal of Game Theory, 6, 129–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalai, E., & Smorodinsky, M. (1975). Other solutions to Nash’s bargaining problem. Econometrica, 43(3), 513–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, M.M. (2000). ’Hydraulic’ rationing. Mathematical Social Sciences 40(2):131–155.

  • Leshem, A., & Zehavi, E. (2006). Bargaining over the interference channel. In: IEEE International Symposium on Information Theory, 2006, pp 2225–2229.

  • Leshem, A., & Zehavi, E. (2008). Cooperative game theory and the Gaussian interference channel. IEEE Journal on Selected Areas in Communications, 26(7), 1078–1088.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livne, Z. A. (1989). Axiomatic characterizations of the Raiffa and the Kalai–Smorodinsky solutions to the bargaining problem. Operations Research, 37(6), 972–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mármol, A. M., & Ponsati, C. (2008). Bargaining over multiple issues with maximin and leximin preferences. Social Choice and Welfare, 30(2), 211–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mjelde, K. M. (1983). Properties of Pareto optimal allocations of resources to activities. Modeling, Identification and Control, 4(3), 167–173. doi:10.4173/mic.1983.3.3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno-Ternero, J. D., & Villar, A. (2006). The tal-family of rules for bankruptcy problems. Social Choice and Welfare, 27(2), 231–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson (1991). Game theory. Analysis of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Nash, J. (1950). The bargaining problem. Econometrica, 18(2), 155–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. (1953). Two-person cooperative games. Econometrica, 21(1), 128–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nemirovski, A. (1996). Interior point polynomial time methods in convex programming. Technion-Israel Institute of Technology, Technion City, Haifa: Lecture Notes-Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management, 32000.

  • O’Neill, B. (1982). A problem of rights arbitration from the talmud. Mathematical Social Sciences, 2(4), 345–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, M. J., & Rubinstein, A. (1990). Bargaining and markets (Vol. 34). San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, H., & Damme, E. V. (1991). Characterizing the Nash and Raiffa bargaining solutions by disagreement point axioms. Mathematics of Operations Research, 16, 447–461.

  • Piniles H (1861). Darkah shel Torah. Vienna.

  • Ponsati, C., & Watson, J. (1997). Multiple-issue bargaining and axiomatic solutions. International Journal of Game Theory, 26(4), 501–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quant, M., Borm, P., Hendrickx, R., & Zwikker, P. (2006). Compromise solutions based on bankruptcy. Mathematical Social Sciences, 51(3), 247–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa, H. (1953). Arbitration schemes for generalized two-person games. Annals of Mathematics Studies, 28, 361–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salonen, H. (1988). Decomposable solutions for n-person bargaining games. European Journal of Political Economy, 4(3), 333–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanimura, E., & Thoron, S. (2008). A mechanism for solving bargaining problems between risk averse players. http://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00325695/.

  • Thomson, W. (2003). Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: A survey. Mathematical Social Sciences, 45(3), 249–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, W. (2008). Two families of rules for the adjudication of conflicting claims. Social Choice and Welfare, 31(4), 667–692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, W. (2012). Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: An update. Tech. rep., mimeo,

  • Thomson, W. (2013a). Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: An update. Tech. rep.: University of Rochester-Center for Economic Research (RCER).

  • Thomson, W. (2013b). Game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: Recent advances. International Game Theory Review, 15(03), 1–60.

  • Trockel W (2009). An axiomatization of the sequential Raiffa solution. A Manuscript, No 425, IMW-Bielefeld University.

  • Trockel, W. (2011). An exact non-cooperative support for the sequential Raiffa solution. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 47(1), 77–83. doi:10.1016/j.jmateco.2010.08.011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trockel, W. (2014a). Axiomatization of the discrete Raiffa solution. Economic Theory Bulletin, 3, 1–9.

  • Trockel, W. (2014b). Robustness of intermediate agreements for the discrete raiffa solution. Games and Economic Behavior, 85, 32–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zehavi, E., & Leshem, A. (2009). Alternative bargaining solutions for the interference channel. In: 3rd IEEE international workshop on computational advances in multi-sensor adaptive processing (CAMSAP), 2009, pp 9–12.

  • Zehavi, E., Leshem, A., Levanda, R., & Han, Z. (2013). Weighted max–min resource allocation for frequency selective channels. IEEE Transactions on Signal Processing, 61(15), 3723–3732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ephraim Zehavi.

Appendices

Appendix

The Linear Programming Solution for 2 Players

For the two player case the linear programming problem can be dramatically simplified, and we provide an \(O(K \log _2 K)\) complexity algorithm (K is the number of assets). We show that the two players share at most a single commodity, regardless of the ratio between the users. To that end let, \(\alpha _{1k}=\alpha _k\), and \(\alpha _{2k}=1-\alpha _k\).

We want to solve the following optimization problem:

$$\begin{aligned} L(\varvec{\alpha }, \varvec{\delta }, \varvec{\mu }, \varvec{\lambda })= & {} -\displaystyle \sum _{k=1}^K(1-\alpha _{k})u_{2k}-\sum _{k=1}^K\mu _{k}\alpha _{k}\nonumber \\&+\,\lambda \left( \sum _{k=1}^K\alpha _{k}u_{1k}-u_1\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(13)

To better understand the problem, we first derive the KKT conditions (Boyd and Vandenberghe 2004). Taking the derivative with respect to \(\alpha _{k}\), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{c} u_{2k}+\lambda u_{1k}- \mu _{k}=0.\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(14)

with the complementarity conditions:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{cl} 1.&{} \sum _{k=1}^K\alpha _{1k} u_{1k}=u_1,\\ 2.&{} \mu _{k}\alpha _{k}=0, \ \mu \ge 0. \end{array}. \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Based on (1415), we can easily see that the Lagrange multipliers in (15) satisfy the following conclusions :

  1. 1.

    \(\mu _{nk}= 0\), if \(\alpha _k>0, \ \forall \ k\) (see (15.2)).

  2. 2.

    If \(0<\alpha _{1k}^j<1\), then the players share an asset p if \(\frac{u_{2p}}{u_{1p}}=-\lambda \) (see (14.2)).

  3. 3.

    Asset p is assigned to player 2 if \(\frac{u_{2p}}{u_{1p}}>-\lambda \).

  4. 4.

    Asset p is assigned to player 1 if \(\frac{u_{2p}}{u_{1p}}<-\lambda \).

  5. 5.

    \(\sum \alpha _{1k}u_{1k}=u_1\).

Assuming that a feasible solution exists and that the assets are ranked in decreasing order according to the ratio \(L\left( k\right) =\frac{u_{1k}}{u_{2k}}\), it follows from the KKT conditions that the allocation is made according to the following rules

  1. 1.

    The ideal point of player 1 is \(I_1\) given by

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} I_1(u_2)= & {} \sum _{k=1}^{p-1}u_{1k}+\alpha _pu_{1p}, \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (16)

    where p and \(\alpha _p\) are set such that

    $$\begin{aligned} u_{2}=\sum _{k=p}^{K}u_{2k}-\alpha _p u_{2p}. \end{aligned}$$
    (17)
  2. 2.

    Similarly, the ideal point of player 2 is \(I_2(u_1)\) is given by

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} I_2(u_1)= & {} \sum _{k=p}^{K}u_{2k}-\alpha _pu_{2p}, \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (18)

    where p and \(\alpha _p\) are set such that

    $$\begin{aligned} u_{1}=\sum _{k=1}^{p-1}u_{1k}+\alpha _pu_{1p}. \end{aligned}$$
    (19)

Therefore, no more than one asset can be shared by the two players. The algorithm for computing the ideal point of player 1 is as follows. Let \(L_k=\frac{u_{1k}}{u_{2k}}\) be the ratio between the utilities of asset k. We can sort the assets in decreasing order according to \(L_K\). If all the values of \(L_{k}\) are distinct, there is at most a single asset that has to be shared between the two players. Since only one asset satisfies Eq. (19), we denote this asset \(k_s\), and all the assets \(1\le k<k_s\) will be allocated to player 1, while all the assets \(k_s < k \le K\) will be be allocated to player 2. Asset \(k_s\) must be shared accordingly between the players. The complexity of this algorithm is at most \(O(K\log K)\), due to the sorting operation. For the Raiffa bargaining solution the sorting operation only has to be done once at the beginning. The complexity of computing the next disagreement point is on the order of O(K).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zehavi, E., Leshem, A. On the Allocation of Multiple Divisible Assets to Players with Different Utilities. Comput Econ 52, 253–274 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10614-017-9673-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10614-017-9673-9

Keywords

Navigation