Skip to main content
Log in

Managing the Risks of Corporate Political Donations: A Utilitarian Perspective

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper applies a utilitarian analysis to corporate political donations. Unlike the more common rights-based analyses, it is argued that the optimal policy is the one that best satisfies society’s rational preferences concerning donor influence, adequate financing, donor pressure and the cost of maintaining and enforcing the democratic system. This analysis suggests that a ban is best if it would be generally observed and sufficient financing from other sources is available, otherwise a donation cap is a better option. Further, lobbyists should be banned from donating small gifts and drafting bills for candidates. The impact of disclosure and other risk management mechanisms are also considered.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. All organisational donations are controversial, but corporate donations are the most controversial and widely discussed. It is beyond the scope of this paper to determine whether all organisations, including unions and non-profit entities, should be treated the same as corporations. One direction future research might take is to ascertain whether non-corporate organisations merit different treatment.

  2. Healthcare provides an example of how the mere fact that a right exists does not mean that society can ensure it is fully promoted. There can be no question that citizens have the right to life and that healthcare is vital to realising that right. However, there is an obvious limit to the amount of resources that the state can spend promoting this right.

  3. These reasons are: (A) to preclude the speech of others is to assume one is infallible; (B) truth is discovered in the collision of various opinions and (C) active and lively debate is the only way to ensure that we are not engaging in dogmatism and prejudice.

  4. Theoretically, the government might try keeping their policies of right violations secret. However, Goodin (1995, pp. 76–77) argues that should the policy of keeping secrets ever be discovered, the disutility caused by people’s worry will be even greater, as there is uncertainty as to how and when such violations will occur. Thus, in order to justify keeping secret a right-violating policy, the utility gains would have to be very high.

  5. It is not possible to source preferences directly as polling data provides insufficient information. A 2007 Gallup Poll survey (Newport and Carroll 2007), for example, found that 47% of 1,001 Americans deemed political action committee funding acceptable; whilst another 47% deemed it unacceptable, but did not identify specific preferences for the donations system.

  6. This comment referred to individual donations, but the point also applies to corporate donations.

  7. The term ‘reasonably expect’ is used because parties cannot reasonably expect to gather sufficient funding if they make no effort to acquire funds.

  8. A US Gallup Poll (Newport and Carroll 2007) surveying 1,001 Americans found that 75% thought that it was inappropriate for Presidential candidates to be receiving campaign contributions from lobbyists. Although poll data are not the most reliable proxy of public preferences and are subject to change, this poll indicates that currently there is a clear public preference to ban lobbyists from donating (at least in the US).

  9. Some social accounting researchers have, however, utilised corporate donation data as a variable when conducting research on a related topic (Roberts et al. 2003; Dwyer and Roberts 2004; Roberts and Bobek 2004; Cho et al. 2006; Cho et al. 2008).

  10. Senates may be structurally undemocratic in multiple ways. In the US, for example, each state is allowed two senators, despite significant differences in population levels. Members of UK House of Lords were traditionally appointed under a hereditary system, although more democratic methods of selection are now gradually being implemented.

References

  • AccountAbility. (2005). Towards responsible lobbying. Available at: www.unglobalcompact.org/docs/news_events/8.1/rl_final.pdf. Accessed 11 May 2006.

  • Ackerman, B., & Ayres, I. (2006). The secret refund booth. The University of Chicago Law Review, 73(4), 1107–1129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, S., & Cavanagh, J. (2000). The rise of corporate global power. Available at: http://www.ips-dc.org/downloads/Top_200.pdf. Accessed 19 December 2007.

  • Barker, D. (2008). Ethics and lobbying: The case of real estate brokerage. Journal of Business Ethics, 80(1), 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, R. F. (2007). Not just a private matter: The purpose of disclosure in an expanded regulatory system. Election Law Journal, 6(1), 38–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, W. (2004). The Dango Tango: Why corruption blocks real reform in Japan. Business Ethics Quarterly, 14(4), 603–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, J. C., Cameron, C. A., & Carter, C. A. (1998). Political action committee contributions and U.S. congressional voting on sugar legislation. American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 80(3), 441–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campaign Disclosure Project. (2008). Grading state disclosure 2008: Evaluating states efforts to bring sunlight to political money. Available at http://www.campaigndisclosure.org/gradingstate/GSD08.pdf. Accessed 22 March 2009.

  • Centre for Political Accountability. (2005). The green canary: Alerting shareholders and protecting their investments. Available at: www.politicalaccountability.net. Accessed 1 August 2007.

  • Cho, C. H., Chen, J. C., & Roberts, R. W. (2008). The politics of environmental disclosure regulation in the chemical and petroleum industries: Evidence from the emergency planning and community right-to-know act of 1986. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 19(4), 450–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cho, C. H., Pattern, D. M., & Roberts, R. W. (2006). Corporate political strategy: An examination of the relation between political expenditures, environmental performance, and environmental disclosure. Journal of Business Ethics, 67(2), 139–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clawson, D., Neustadtl, A., & Weller, M. (1998). Dollars and votes how business campaign contributions subvert democracy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colvin, M., & Metherell, L. (2012). Political donations data rekindles call for reform. Available at: http://www.abc.net.au/pm/content/2012/s3420798.htm. Accessed 15 February 2012.

  • Davis-Denny, G. (2005). Divergent disclosure: The value of uniformity in state campaign finance disclosure laws. Election Law Journal, 4(4), 282–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De George, R. (1993). Competing with integrity in international business. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubs, C. (2005). Political donations by companies: A corporate law perspective. Cross-sections, 1(1), 16–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue. London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, P. D., & Roberts, R. W. (2004). Known by the company they keep: A study of political campaign contributions made by the United States public accounting profession. Critical Perspectives on Accounting, 15(6–7), 865–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, T. (1995). Industries affected by endangered species act help a senator rewrite its provisions. The New York Times, 20.

  • Ferdinand, P. (2003). Party funding and political corruption in East Asia: The cases of Japan, South Korea and Taiwan. In R. Austin & M. Tjernström (Eds.), Funding of political parties and campaign elections (pp. 55–69). Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogg, K., Molutsi, P., & Tjernström, M. (2003). Conclusion. In R. Austin & M. Tjernström (Eds.), Funding of political parties and campaign elections. Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance.

  • Fora.tv. (2007). A troubling nexus: Big money and politics (transcript). Available at: http://fora.tv/fora/fora_transcript_pdf.php?cid=1024. Accessed 6 June 2007.

  • Garrett, E., & Smith, D. A. (2005). Veiled political actors and campaign disclosure laws in direct democracy. Election Law Journal, 4(4), 295–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (1995). Utilitarianism as a public philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grattan, M. (2005). Political guns for hire. Available at: http://www.theage.com.au/news/Michelle-Grattan/Political-guns-for-hire/2005/05/24/1116700707853.html. Accessed 1 October 2007.

  • Gray, R. (2002). The social accounting project and Accounting Organisations and Society: Privileging engagement, imaginings, new accountings and pragmatism over critique? Accounting, Organizations and Society, 27(7), 687–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, R. (2005). Taking a long view of what we now know about social and environmental accountability and reporting. Electronic Journal of Radical Organisation Theory, 9(1), 3–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, R., & Guthrie, J. (2007). Social accounting, mega accounting and beyond: A festschrift in honour of M.R. Mathews. St. Andrews: CSEAR Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, J. B., I. I. I., & Hoch, D. (1997). Ethical standards for business lobbying: Some practical suggestions. Business Ethics Quarterly, 7(3), 117–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hargreaves, J. (2008). Risk: The ethics of a creative curriculum. Innovations in Education and Teaching International, 45(3), 227–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hourigan, B. (2006). Who pays? Political donations and democratic accountability. IPA Review, 58(3), 12–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • International Accounting Standards Board: (2010). Conceptual framework for financial reporting 2010. London, UK: IFRS Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2005). Political finance policy, parties and democratic development. Available at: http://www.accessdemocracy.org/library/1949_polpart_johnston_110105.pdf. Accessed 11 June 2008.

  • Joo, T. (2002). Corporate governance and the constitutionality of campaign finance reform. Election Law Journal, 1(3), 361–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, D., Caplan, A. L., & Merz, J. F. (2003). All gifts large and small: Toward an understanding of the ethics of pharmaceutical industry gift giving. The American Journal of Bioethics, 3(3), 39–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korten, D. C. (2001). When corporations rule the world. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamberton, G. (2005). Sustainability accounting—A brief history and a conceptual framework. Accounting Forum, 29(1), 7–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lascelles, D. (2005). The ethics of influence: Political donations and lobbying. London: Institute of Business Ethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leigh, A. (2004). Blind trusts for political gifts are a surer bet than trusting blindly. The Sydney Morning Herald.

  • Leong, S. (2009). Submission concerning the electoral reform green paper 2008. Available at: http://www.pmc.gov.au/consultation/elect_reform/pdfs/sub19.pdf. Accessed 8 August 2009.

  • Lourie, D. (2009). Rethinking donor disclosure after the proposition 8 campaign. Southern California Law Review, 133(1), 133–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, R. M. (1997). Twenty-five years of social and environmental accounting research: Is there are silver jubilee to celebrate? Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 10(4), 481–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, R. M. (2004). Developing a matrix approach to categorise the social and environmental accounting research literature. Qualitative Research in Accounting and Management, 1(1), 30–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, D. (2007). Kasky V. Nike and the quarrelsome question of corporate free speech. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(1), 65–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee, R. W. (2008a). Applying ethics to insider trading. Journal of Business Ethics, 77(2), 205–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee, R. W. (2008b). Ethical aspects of using government to subvert competition: Antidumping laws as a case study of rent seeking activity. Journal of Business Ethics, 83(4), 759–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNamee, M. J., Sheridan, H., & Buswell, J. (2001). The limits of utilitarianism as a professional ethic in public sector leisure policy and provision. Leisure Studies, 20(3), 173–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2005). Do CEOs get paid too much? Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(2), 257–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mutch, R. (2006). Before and after Bellotti: The corporate political contributions cases. Election Law Journal, 5(3), 293–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nace, T. (2003). Gangs of America—The rise of corporate power and the disabling of democracy. Available at: http://gangsofamerica.com/read.html. Accessed 22 June 2009.

  • Nassmacher, K.-H. (2003a). The funding of political parties in the Anglo-Saxon Orbit. In R. Austin & M. Tjernström (Eds.), Funding of political parties and campaign elections (pp. 33–52). Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nassmacher, K.-H. (2003b). Introduction: Political parties, funding and democracy. In R. Austin & M. Tjernström (Eds.), Funding of political parties and campaign elections (pp. 1–19). Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newport, F., & Carroll, J. (2007). Most say that presidential candidates should refuse lobbyist money. Available at: http://www.gallup.com/poll/28543/most-say-presidential-candidates-should-refuse-lobbyist-money.aspx. Accessed 18 June 2011.

  • Norton, A. (2011). Democracy and money: The dangers of campaign finance reform. Available at: http://www.cis.org.au/images/stories/policy-monographs/pm-119.pdf. Accessed 13 June 2011.

  • Orr, G. (2004). Australian electoral systems—How well do they serve political equality? Available at: http://democratic.audit.anu.edu.au. Accessed 7 October 2007.

  • Ostas, D. T. (2007). The law and ethics of K Street: Lobbying, the First Amendment, and the duty to create just laws. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(1), 33–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owen, D. (2008). Chronicles of wasted time?: A personal reflection on the current state of, and future prospects for, social and environmental accounting research. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 21(2), 240–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, L. D. (2005). Social and environmental accountability research: A view from the commentary box. Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 18(6), 842–860.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pava, M. L., & Krausz, J. (1995). Criteria for evaluating the legitimacy of corporate social responsibility projects. National conference on ethical issues in finance, University of Florida, January 1995.

  • Pierre, J., Svåsand, L., & Widfeldt, A. (2000). State subsidies to political parties: Confronting rhetoric with reality. West European Politics, 29(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinto-Duschinsky, M. (2002). Financing politics: A global view. Journal of Democracy, 13(4), 69–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsay, I., Stapleton, G., & Vernon, J. (2000). Political donations by Australian companies. Available at: http://cclsr.law.unimelb.edu.au/research-papers/Monograph%20Series/Political%20Donations%20final.pdf. Accessed 28 March 2007.

  • Roberts, R. W., & Bobek, D. D. (2004). The politics of tax accounting in the United States: Evidence from the taxpayer relief act of 1997. Accounting, Organizations and Society, 29(5–6), 565–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. W., Dwyer, P. D., & Sweeney, J. T. (2003). Political strategies used by the US public accounting profession during auditor liability reform: The case of the private securities litigation reform act of 1995. Journal of Accounting and Public Policy, 22(5), 433–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Select Committee on Electoral and Political Party Funding. (2008). Electoral and political party funding in New South Wales. Available at: http://www.parliament.nsw.gov.au/Prod/parlment/committee.nsf/0/1CA6D5A89FABD975CA25746D00063640. Accessed 24 November 2008.

  • Sitkoff, R. H. (2003). Politics and the business corporation: Do politicians want donations more than corporations want to give them? Regulation, 26(4), 30–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1998). An Inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. A. (1999). Some problems of taxpayer funded political campaigns. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 148(2), 591–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. A. (2003). Campaign finance reform: Searing for corruption in all the wrong places. Available at: http://www.cato.org/pubs/scr/2003/finance.pdf. Accessed 6 October 2007.

  • Sobel, D. (1998). Well being as the object of moral consideration. Economics and Philosophy, 14(2), 249–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Standing Senate Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs. (2006). Issue 6—Evidence, September 8, 2006. Available at: http://www.parl.gc.ca/39/1/parlbus/commbus/senate/Com-e/lega-e/06evc-e.htm?Language=E&Parl=39&Ses=1&comm_id=11. Accessed 11 February 2008.

  • Stark, A. (2010). Business in politics: Lobbying and corporate campaign contributions. In G. G. Brenkert & T. L. Beauchamp (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of business ethics (pp. 501–532). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephan, M. (2002). Environmental information disclosure programs: They work but why? Social Science Quarterly, 83(1), 190–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoll, M. L. (2005). Corporate rights to free speech? Journal of Business Ethics, 58(1–3), 261–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tham, J.-C. (2003). Campaign finance reform in Australia: Some reasons for reform. In G. Orr, B. Mercurio, & G. Williams (Eds.), Realising democracy: Electoral law in Australia (pp. 114–129). Sydney: The Federation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unerman, J., Bebbington, J., & O’Dwyer, B. (2007). Sustainability accounting and accountability. Oxon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webber, L. J. (1997). Ethics and the political activity of business: Reviewing the agenda. Business Ethics Quarterly, 7(3), 71–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilcox, C. (2005). Designing campaign finance disclosure in the states: Tracing the tributaries of campaign finance. Election Law Journal, 4(4), 371–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodstock Theological Center. (2002). The ethics of lobbying: Organized interests, political power, and the common good. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, S., & Tham, J.-C. (2006). Political finance in Australia: A skewed and secret system. Available at: http://democratic.audit.anu.edu.au/papers/focussed_audits/20061121_youngthamfin.pdf. Accessed 8 March.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We wish to thank Gordon Boyce, Cary Di Lernia, Lorne Cummings, Dennis Arnold, anonymous reviewers and the delegates of the 6th Australasian Conference on Social and Environmental Accounting Research who provided valuable feedback on earlier drafts of this paper. We also wish to acknowledge financial support of Macquarie University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shane Leong.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Leong, S., Hazelton, J. & Townley, C. Managing the Risks of Corporate Political Donations: A Utilitarian Perspective. J Bus Ethics 118, 429–445 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-012-1592-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-012-1592-z

Keywords

Navigation