Skip to main content
Log in

Business Ethics and the ‘End of History’ in Corporate Law

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Henry Hansmann has claimed we have reached the “end of history” in corporate law, organized around the “widespread normative consensus that corporate managers should act exclusively in the economic interests of shareholders.” In this paper, I examine Hansmann’s own argument in support of this view, in order to draw out its implications for some of the traditional concerns of business ethicists about corporate social responsibility. The centerpiece of Hansmann’s argument is the claim that ownership of the firm is most naturally exercised by the group able to achieve the lowest agency costs, and that homogeneity of interest within the ownership group is the most important factor in achieving lower costs. He defends this claim through a study of cooperatives, attempting to show that homogeneity is the source of the competitive advantage most often enjoyed by shareholders over other constituency groups, such as workers, suppliers and customers, when it comes to exercising control over the firm. Some business ethicists, impressed by this argument, have taken it to be a vindication of Milton Friedman’s claim that profit-maximization is the only “social responsibility” of management. I would like to suggest that this conclusion does not follow, and that the “Hansmann argument” lends itself to a less minimalist view, what I refer to as a “market failures” approach to business ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The problem for stakeholder theory is sufficiently evident that Hansmann dedicates only two paragraphs of The Ownership of Enterprise to it (2000, p. 44). There is a more ample discussion in Hansmann and Kraakman (2003).

  2. For my own contribution, see Heath (2006a, b).

  3. Hansmann writes: “I use the term ‘cost-minimizing’ here to mean ‘efficient’ in the economist’s very broad sense of that word—that is, to refer to a situation in which there is no alternative arrangement that could make any class of patrons better off, by their own subjective valuation, without making some other class worse off to a greater degree” (2000, p. 23).

  4. Boatright writes, “Whether a corporation is owned by investors, employees, customers, suppliers, or some other constituency is determined by the costs and benefits of ownership as reflected in the market choices made by each group. The standard argument holds that whatever the assignment of ownership, the resulting system of corporate governance is optimal not only for the constituency with control and a claim on the residual but also for all other constituencies” (2002, p. 48).

  5. Kent Greenfield summarizes the argument as follows: “Shareholders do not have a complete ‘bundle of rights’ to make them ‘owners’ in the traditional sense, nor are they owners in any other way that would distinguish their contribution to the firm from the contributions of other stakeholders” (2006, p. 126). The force of this argument, he argues, is the reason that “no prominent contemporary corporate law scholar uses property rights as the primary rationale for shareholder dominance” (2006, p. 47).

  6. It follows, he says, that “the shareholder–management relation is not ‘ethically different’ for any reason that is unique to that relation” (Boatright 1994, p. 403).

  7. For a response to this argument, see Philips et al. (2003). They assert that “Managerial opportunism is a problem, but it is no more a problem for stakeholder theory than the alternative. Indeed, there may be reason to believe stakeholder theory more resistant to managerial self-dealing” (p. 484). The argument presented in support of this claim, however, is entirely hypothetical, based on speculation about how managers and stakeholder groups might respond to the incentives they face. Hansmann, by contrast, offers empirical considerations in support of his view. For a similar argument, that looks rather to the public sector for empirical evidence regarded the effects of multiprincipal agency problems, see Heath and Norman (2004).

  8. This is for simplicity of presentation. It does not affect the results if one imagines the firm already being owned by one group, entertaining bids for a transfer of control to some other.

References

  • Bakan, J. (2004). The corporation. Toronto: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berle, A. A., & Means G. C. (1991) [1932]. The modern corporation and private property. London: Transaction.

  • Blair, M. M. (1999). Firm-specific human capital and theories of the firm. In M. M. Blair & M. J. Roe (Eds.), Employees and corporate governance. Washington: Brookings Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, M. M., & Stout, L. A. (1999). A team production theory of corporate law. Virginia Law Review, 85, 248–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (1994). Fiduciary duties and the shareholder–management relation: Or, what’s so special about shareholders? Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 393–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (1999). Ethics in finance. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (2002). Ethics and corporate governance: justifying the role of the stakeholder. In N. Bowie (Ed.), Blackwell companion to business ethics. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (2006). What’s wrong—and what’s right—with stakeholder management. Journal of Private Enterprise, 21, 106–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, R. C. (1985). Agency costs versus fiduciary duties. In J. W. Pratt & R. J. Zeckhauser (Eds.), Principals and agents. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R. (1985). A preface to economic democracy. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterbrook, F. H., & Fischel, D. R. (1991). The economic structure of corporate law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (1994). The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 409–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E., & Evan, W. M. (1990). Corporate governance: A stakeholder interpretation. Journal of Behavioral Economics, 19, 337–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gates, J. (1998). The ownership solution. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K. (1991). Business ethics and stakeholder analysis. Business Ethics Quarterly, 1, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenfield, K. (2006). The failure of corporate law. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansmann, H. (2000). The ownership of enterprise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansmann, H., & Kraakman, R. H. (2000). Abstract of “The end of history for corporate law”. http://papers.ssrn.com/paper.taf?abstract_id=204528.

  • Hansmann, H., & Kraakman, R. H. (2003). The end of history for corporate law. In J. Gordon & M. Roe (Eds.), Convergence and persistence in corporate governance. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, O. (1995). Firms, contracts and financial structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2001). The efficient society. Toronto: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2006a). Business ethics without stakeholders. Business Ethics Quarterly, 16, 533–557.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2006b). An adversarial ethic for business: Or, when Sun-Tzu met the stakeholder. Journal of Business Ethics, 72, 359–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J., & Norman, W. (2004). Stakeholder theory, corporate governance, and public management. Journal of Business Ethics, 53, 247–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honoré, A. M. (1961). Ownership. In A. G. Guest (Ed.), Oxford essays in jurisprudnece. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. C. (2002). Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly, 12, 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. C., & Meckling, W. H. (1976). Theory of the firm: Managerial behavior, agency costs and ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3, 305–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornai, J. (1992). The socialist system. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kraakman, R., Davies, P., Hansmann, H., Hertig, G., Hopt, K. J., Kanda, H., et al. (2004). The anatomy of corporate law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, I. B. (2006). Corporate law and the role of corporations in society: Monism, pluralism, markets and politics. Canadian Bar Review, 85, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maitland, I. (1994). The morality of the corporation: An empirical or normative disagreement? Business Ethics Quarterly, 4, 445–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcoux, A. (2003). A fiduciary argument against stakeholder theory. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13, 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marens, R., & Wicks, A. (1999). Getting real: Stakeholder theory, managerial practice, and the general irrelevance of fiduciary duties owed to shareholders. Business Ethics Quarterly, 9, 273–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1981). Market neutrality and the failure of cooperatives. British Journal of Political Science, 11, 309–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (1999). Tinged shareholder theory: Or what’s so special about stakeholders. Business Ethics: A European Review, 8, 117–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, W., & Macdonald, C. (2003). Getting to the bottom of the triple bottom line. Business Ethics Quarterly, 14, 243–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orts, E. (1998). Shirking and sharking: A legal theory of the firm. Yale Law and Policy Review, 16, 265–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orts, E. W., & Strudler, A. (2009). Putting a stake in stakeholder theory. Journal of Business Ethics, 88, 605–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Philips, R., Freeman, R. E., & Wicks, A. C. (2003). What stakeholder theory is not. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13, 479–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robé, J.-P. (2011). The legal structure of the firm. Accounting, Economics and Law, 1, 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stout, L. A. (2008). Why we should stop teaching Dodge v. Ford. Virginia Law and Business Review, 3, 163–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (1981). The economics of organization: The transaction cost approach. The American Journal of Sociology, 87, 548–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Heath.

Additional information

The development of this paper has benefited from discussions with John Boatright, Margaret Blair, Wayne Norman, Alexei Marcoux, Eric Orts, Alan Strudler, members of the Legal Studies and Business Ethics program at the Wharton School of Business, as well as participants in the Trans-Atlantic Business Ethics Conference held at York University.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Heath, J. Business Ethics and the ‘End of History’ in Corporate Law. J Bus Ethics 102 (Suppl 1), 5–20 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1192-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-011-1192-3

Keywords

Navigation