Skip to main content
Log in

The proximate–ultimate distinction and evolutionary developmental biology: causal irrelevance versus explanatory abstraction

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Mayr’s proximate–ultimate distinction has received renewed interest in recent years. Here we discuss its role in arguments about the relevance of developmental to evolutionary biology. We show that two recent critiques of the proximate–ultimate distinction fail to explain why developmental processes in particular should be of interest to evolutionary biologists. We trace these failures to a common problem: both critiques take the proximate–ultimate distinction to neglect specific causal interactions in nature. We argue that this is implausible, and that the distinction should instead be understood in the context of explanatory abstractions in complete causal models of evolutionary change. Once the debate is reframed in this way, the proximate–ultimate distinction’s role in arguments against the theoretical significance of evo-devo is seen to rely on a generally implicit premise: that the variation produced by development is abundant, small and undirected. We show that a “lean version” of the proximate–ultimate distinction can be maintained even when this isotropy assumption does not hold. Finally, we connect these considerations to biological practice. We show that the investigation of developmental constraints in evolutionary transitions has long relied on a methodology which foregrounds the explanatory role of developmental processes. It is, however, entirely compatible with the lean version of the proximate–ultimate distinction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It has recently been suggested by several authors that ultimate questions should be restricted to issues of adaptive rationale or “what for?” (Haig 2013; Gardner 2013). To some extent, this is a dispute about preferred linguistic usage. However, in the spirit of Gould and Lewontin (1979) we prefer to include all evolutionary processes in the ultimate category. This includes selection, drift, developmental constraints, and more. Which of these processes are the most relevant should then be investigated as an empirical matter on a case by case basis.

  2. Similar arguments could be made for other processes that have an effect on variational isotropy, such as variation in mutation rates (Hodgkinson and Eyre-Walker 2011).

  3. Gould (1989) argued valiantly that “constraint” should be understood not only in the negative sense of limiting the power of selection, but also in the positive sense of channeling evolutionary transitions in particular adaptive directions. It seems that this usage has not been widely adopted; the more recent term “developmental drive” (Arthur 2001) appears to have been received more favorably for the positive case. Both constraints and drive, however, have the same conceptual foundation: If the variation available to selection is strongly structured by developmental mechanisms, then evolutionary transitions will need to be explained by asking both which variants were selectively advantageous and which variants were produced in the first place.

  4. We thank Günter Wagner for suggesting this example.

References

  • Alberch P (1982) Developmental constraints in evolutionary processes. In: Bonner JT (ed) Evolution and development. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 313–332

  • Alberch P (1985) Developmental constraints: why St. Bernards often have an extra digit and poodles never do. Am Nat 126(3):430–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alberch P, Gale EA (1985) A developmental analysis of an evolutionary trend: digital reduction in amphibians. Evolution 39(1):8–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (1994) Two concepts of constraint: adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology. Philos Sci 61(4):556–578. http://www.jstor.org/stable/188335

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought. Roots of Evo-Devo. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A (2003) Ernst Mayr’s’ ultimate/proximate’ distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biol Philos 18(4):553–565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur W (2001) Developmental drive: an important determinant of the direction of phenotypic evolution. Evol Dev 3(4):271–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty J (1994) The proximate/ultimate distinction in the multiple careers of Ernst Mayr. Biol Philos 9(3):333–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2010) Beyond reduction and pluralism: toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis 73(3):295–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calcott B (2013) Why how and why aren’t enough: more problems with Mayr’s proximate–ultimate distinction. Biol Philos 28:767–780

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1859) On the origin of species. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickins TE, Barton RA (2012) Reciprocal causation and the proximate–ultimate distinction. Biol Philos 28:747–756

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (1998) Evolutionary biology. Sinauer Associates Incorporated, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A (2013) Ultimate explanations concern the adaptive rationale for organism design. Biol Philos 28:787–791

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gompel N, Prud’homme B, Wittkopp PJ, Kassner VA, Carroll SB (2005) Chance caught on the wing: cis-regulatory evolution and the origin of pigment patterns in drosophila. Nature 433(7025):481–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1983) The hardening of the modern synthesis. In: Grene M (ed) Dimensions of Darwinism: themes and counter themes in twentieth-century evolutionary theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1989) A developmental constraint in cerion, with comments of the definition and interpretation of constraint in evolution. Evolution 43(3):516–539

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (2002) The structure of evolutionary theory. Harvard University Press, Harvard

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of san marco and the panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc Biol Sci 205(1161):581–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2013) Proximate and ultimate causes: how come? And what for? Biol Philos Biol Philos 28(5):781–786

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochman A (2012) The phylogeny fallacy and the ontogeny fallacy. Biol Philos 28(4):593–612

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkinson A, Eyre-Walker A (2011) Variation in the mutation rate across mammalian genomes. Nat Rev Genet 12(11):756–766

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knell S, Weber M (2009) Menschliches Leben. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Sterelny K, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2011) Adaptive evolution of pelvic reduction in sticklebacks by recurrent deletion of a pitx1 enhancer. Science 334(6062):1512–1516

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, Hoppitt W, Uller T (2012) More on how and why: cause and effect in biology revisited. Biol Philos 28(5):1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Love A (2006) Evolutionary morphology and evo-devo: hierarchy and novelty. Theory Biosci 124(3–4):317–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 67(1):1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith J, Burian R, Kauffman S, Alberch P (1985) Developmental constraints and evolution: a perspective from the mountain lake conference on development and evolution. Q Rev Biol 60(3):265–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1961) Cause and effect in biology. Science 134(3489):1501–1506. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1707986

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1984) The triumph of evolutionary synthesis. Times Lit Suppl 2:1261–1262

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1997) The objects of selection. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 94(6):2091–2094

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (2003) The development of animal form. Ontogeny, morphology, and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Boudry M (2013) Prove it! The burden of proof game in science vs. pseudoscience disputes. Philosophia. doi:10.1007/s11406-013-9500-z

  • Prud’homme B, Gompel N, Carroll SB (2007) Emerging principles of regulatory evolution. Proc Natl Acad Sci 104(S1):8605–8612

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1998) Six sayings about adaptationism. In: Hull DL, Ruse M (eds) The philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2000) What is the promise of developmental evolution? Part I: why is developmental biology necessary to explain evolutionary innovations? J Exp Zool 288(2):95–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2001) What is the promise of developmental evolution? Part II: a causal explanation of evolutionary innovations may be impossible. J Exp Zool 291(4):305–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP, Larsson HCE (2003) What is the promise of developmental evolution? III. The crucible of developmental evolution. J Exp Zool Part B Mol Dev Evol 300(1):1–4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace B (1986) Can embryologists contribute to an understanding of evolutionary mechanisms? In: Bechtel W (ed) Integrating scientific disciplines. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2005) Phenotypic accommodation: adaptive innovation due to developmental plasticity. J Exp Zool Part B Mol Dev Evol 304B(6):610–618

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An early version of this paper was presented at the second meeting of the European Society for Evolutionary Developmental Biology in Ghent, Belgium, in 2008. We are particularly grateful to the following for comments on earlier drafts of the paper: Mark Jonas, Kärin Nickelsen, Tim Räz, and the members of the Lake Geneva Biology Interest Group (LG-BIG). We have also greatly benefitted from the comments of an anonymous referee for Biology & Philosophy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raphael Scholl.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Scholl, R., Pigliucci, M. The proximate–ultimate distinction and evolutionary developmental biology: causal irrelevance versus explanatory abstraction. Biol Philos 30, 653–670 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9427-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9427-1

Keywords

Navigation