Skip to main content
Log in

Organizational requirements for multicellular autonomy: insights from a comparative case study

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we explore the organizational conditions underlying the emergence of organisms at the multicellular level. More specifically, we shall propose a general theoretical scheme according to which a multicellular organism is an ensemble of cells that effectively regulates its own development through collective (meta-cellular) mechanisms of control of cell differentiation and cell division processes. This theoretical result derives from the detailed study of the ontogenetic development of three multicellular systems (Nostoc punctiforme, Volvox carteri and Strongylocentrotus purpuratus) and, in particular, of their corresponding cell-to-cell signaling networks. The case study supports our claim that a specific type of functional integration among the cells of a multicellular ensemble (namely, a regulatory control system consisting in several inter-cellular mechanisms that modulate epigenesis and whose operation gets decoupled from the intra-cellular metabolic machinery), is required for it to qualify as a proper organism. Finally, we argue why a multicellular system exhibiting this type of functionally differentiated and integrated developmental organization becomes a self-determining collective entity and, therefore, should be considered as a second-order autonomous system.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For instance, the ‘spatial boundedness’ of Stelreny and Griffiths (1999), the ‘unitary organism’ concept of Santelices (1999), the ‘paradigm organism’ concept of Wilson (1999), or the ‘functional integration’ concept, as discussed by Wilson and Sober (1989) and by Ruiz Mirazo et al. (2000), are examples of such criteria.

  2. With the term ‘epigenetic’ we mean processes/mechanisms by which a heritable change is induced in the genetic system of a cell and/or a cell lineage that does not involve a change in the nucleotide sequence but affects the spatio-temporal modulation of the developmental transformation of those cells.

  3. Another very important aspect that should be considered, in this context, is the emergence of ‘agency’ at the whole system level: i.e., the emergence of the capacity to deal (as an integrated collective unit) with the environment. However, due to lack of space, in this contribution we will not consider that interactive dimension of an organism, relevant both in minimal or more complex forms of it, as it has been highlighted by several authors (see e.g. Hooker 2009).

  4. In N. punctiforme the vegetative cells can also develop into akinetes, spore-like structures that are more resistant to cold and desiccation conditions, and into hormogonium filaments, which lack heterocysts, have smaller size and a slow gliding motility, used for short-distance dispersal. Akinete and hormogonium development are strictly triggered by environmental signals followed—in the latter case—by multiple independent (intracellularly controlled) cell divisions resulting in one cell type in the filament (see Meeks et al. 2002 for details). It is for those reasons that we do not consider these modalities in our analysis of N. punctiforme.

  5. There are also other signals that affect developmental direction, but they are always acting intracellularly and downstream the main activator and inhibitor, and independently within each cell (see Fig. 2). Therefore, they are not relevant to our analysis and are not discussed here.

  6. The only case would be a diffused PatS from an NtcA-activated cell at a distant area of the filament, which will most probably not be sufficient to compensate for the loss of PatS (see Meeks et al. 2002; Kumar et al. 2010).

  7. Volvox carteri embryos first cleave symmetrically five times to form a 32-cell embryo with identical cells, and then 16 cells divide asymmetrically to produce one large gonidial ‘cell initial’ and one small somatic ‘cell initial’ each. The first gonidial cells divide twice again asymmetrically and produce additional somatic initials at each division. The gonidial initials then temporarily stop any cleavage activity (i.e. they stop dividing, in what is called ‘bifurcation of the cell division program’), while the somatic initials continue to divide symmetrically about three more times (see Kirk 1998 for details).

  8. In the case of a gls gene mutation, all cells will keep on dividing symmetrically becoming somatic cells, as they are too small to undergo gonidial specification. From our present knowledge on this system, RegA is the single responsible gene for a complete and stable germ/soma separation (see Fig 3). It operates by repressing chloroplast biogenesis—thus preventing somatic cells from growing enough to trigger cell division. RegA mutants will follow the path of their unicellular ancestral, beginning as small flagellated cells and then re-differentiating as gonidia. On the contrary, lag genes act in gonidia to prevent the development of somatic features, such as flagella and eyespots.

  9. The construction of its endomesoderm gene regulatory network (GRN), pertaining to both intra- and inter-cellular signals (up to 30 h post-fertilization), is currently the largest and most detailed network described in any embryo, which is constantly updated (for more details, check the website: http://sugp.caltech.edu/endomes/#UpTo30NetworkDiagram).

  10. The molecular details of the respective mechanisms of genomic developmental control can be found in Ben-Tabou de-Leon and Davidson (2007), Oliveri et al. (2008), Peter and Davidson (2009, 2010, 2011).

  11. See Folse and Roughgarden (2010, pp. 452–453) for a relevant analysis for Volvox carteri. In N. punctiforme things are not significantly different, since in the case of heterocysts development it can be said that there is an exportation of fitness at the level of the whole group.

  12. Throughout embryogenesis all the cells of the embryo are linked by cytoplasmic bridges that are formed as a result of incomplete cytokinesis and break down after embryogenesis. However, this is enough for the pole of each one of the somatic cells to be oriented with respect to the head of the spheroid, so that coordinated swimming and efficient phototaxis could take place (see Kaiser 2001; Kirk 2005 for details). This could be considered as an example of intercellular communication during the developmental process, but obviously not of the kind exhibited by the Sea Urchin case, since it is only happening among cells of the same lineage (somatic cells), it is of a very rigid nature, and it does not affect cell differentiation.

  13. Like eukaryotes, prokaryotic cells show also certain forms of epigenetic control. However, their capacity for inducing differentiation is considerably weaker than that of eukaryotic cells. Actually, there is a strong difference between MC entities formed by prokaryotic cells or by eukaryotic ones, because in these latter cells, in particular, thanks to the nucleation of DNA, there is (among other things) the possibility for more elaborated regulation and processing of genetic information (see Mattick 2004).

  14. There could be many other functional constraints contributing to the constitutive processes and maintenance of the whole MC entity (i.e., symbionts, indirect action of other organisms, etc), but these constraints, as explained in section “Functionally integrated MC organizations through dynamically decoupled developmental regulatory controls”, do not belong to the same level than those we have studied (namely, those constraints regulating epigenetic mechanisms of cellular differentiation and which are decoupled from metabolic-interactive processes).

  15. Rosslenbroich (2009) also discusses several reasons according to which Eumetazoans achieve much higher degrees of ‘autonomization’ from the environment, in the sense that the direct influences from it are gradually reduced, while at the same time “many interconnections with and dependencies upon” the environment are retained, and a stabilization of self-referential, intrinsic functions within the system is generated.

References

  • Angerer RC, Angerer LM (2012) Sea urchin embryo: specification of cell fates. eLS. Wiley, Chichester. doi:10.1002/9780470015902.a0001513.pub3

  • Bechtel W (2007) Biological mechanisms: organized to maintain autonomy. In: Boogerd F, Bruggeman F, Hofmeyr JH, Westerhoff HV (eds) Systems biology. Philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 269–302

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bell G, Mooers AO (1997) Size and complexity among multicellular organisms. Biol J Linn Soc 60:345–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Tabou de-Leon S, Davidson EH (2007) Gene regulation: gene control network in development. Annu Rev Biophys Biomol Struct 36:191–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bondos S (2006) Variations on a theme: Hox and Wnt combinatorial regulation during animal development. Sci STKE 2006(355):pe38

  • Bonner JT (1999) The origins of multicellularity. Integr Biol 1:27–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonner JT (2000) First signals: the evolution of multicellular development. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss LW (1987) The evolution of individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell EL, Summers ML, Christman H, Martin ME, Meeks JC (2007) Global gene expression patterns of Nostoc punctiforme in steady-state dinitrogen-grown heterocyst-containing cultures and at single time points during the differentiation of akinetes and hormogonia. J Bacteriol 189:5247–5256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll SB (2001) Chance and necessity: the evolution of morphological complexity and diversity. Nature 409:1102–1109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christman HD, Campbell EL, Meeks JC (2011) Global transcription profiles of the nitrogen stress response resulting in heterocyst or hormogonium development in Nostoc punctiforme. J Bacteriol 193(24):6874–6886

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E (2011) The problem of biological individuality. Biol Theory 5(4):312–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa S, Shaw P (2007) ‘Open minded’ cells: how cells can change fate. Trends Cell Biol 17:101–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson EH (2010) Emerging properties of animal gene regulatory networks. Nature 468:911–920

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J, O’Malley MA (2009) Varieties of living things: life at the intersection of lineage and metabolism. Philos Theory Biol 1:e003

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M, Pedroso M (2013) Biological individuality: the case of biofilms. Biol Philos 28(2):331–349

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erwin DH, Davidson EH (2009) The evolution of hierarchical gene regulatory networks. Nat Rev Genet 10:141–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flemming H, Wingender J (2010) The biofilm matrix. Nat Rev Microbiol 8:623–633

    Google Scholar 

  • Folse HJ III, Roughgarden J (2010) What is an individual organism? A multilevel selection perspective. Q Rev Biol 85(4):447–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A (2009) Adaptation as organism design. Biol Lett 5(6):861–864

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, Grafen A (2009) Capturing the superorganism: a formal theory of group adaptation. J Evol Biol 22(4):659–671

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart J, Kirschner M (1997) Cells, embryos, and evolution. Blackwell Science, Malden, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallmann A (2011) Evolution of reproductive development in the volvocine algae. Sex Plant Reprod 24:97–112. doi:10.1007/s00497-010-0158-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker C (2009) Interaction and bio-cognitive order. Synthese 166:513–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser D (2001) Building a multicellular organism. Annu Rev Genet 35:103–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk DL (1998) Volvox: molecular-genetic origins of multicellularity and cellular differentiation. Developmental and cell biology series. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirk DL (2005) A twelve-step program for evolving multicellularity and a division of labor. BioEssays 27:299–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk MM, Ransick A, McRae SE, Kirk DL (1993) The relationship between cell size and cell fate in Volvox carteri. J Cell Biol 123:191–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar K, Mella Herrera AR, Golden WJ (2010) Cyanobacterial Heterocysts. Cold Spring Harb Perspect Biol. doi:10.1101/cshperspect.a000315

    Google Scholar 

  • Maldener I, Muro Pastor AM (2010) Cyanobacterial heterocysts. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences (ELS). Wiley, Chichester. doi:10.1002/9780470015902.a0000306.pub2

  • Materna SC, Davidson EH (2012) Comprehensive analysis of Delta signaling in pre-gastrular sea urchin embryos. Dev Biol 364:77–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mattick J (2004) The hidden genetic program of complex organisms. Sci Am 291(4):60–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1973) De Máquinas y Seres Vivos—Una teoría sobre la organización biológica. Editorial Universitaria S.A, Santiago de Chile

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1987) The tree of knowledge: the biological roots of human understanding. Shambhala Publications, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1986) The problems of biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. Freeman, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McFall-Ngai MJ (1999) Consequences of evolving with bacterial symbionts: insights from the squid-vibrio associations. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 30:235–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meeks JC, Campbell EL, Summers ML, Wong FC (2002) Cellular differentiation in the cyanobacterium Nostoc punctiforme. Arch Microbiol 178:395–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michod RE (1999) Darwinian dynamics: evolutionary transitions in fitness and individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod RE (2005) On the transfer of fitness from the cell to the multicellular organism. Biol Philos 20:967–987

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno A, Ruiz-Mirazo K (2009) The problem of the emergence of functional diversity in prebiotic evolution. Biol Philos 24(5):585–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno A, Ruiz-Mirazo K, Barandiaran, XE (2011) The impact of the paradigm of complexity on the foundational frameworks of biology and cognitive science. In: Hooker CA (ed) Philosophy of Complex Systems. Vol. X of the Gavia D, Thagard P, Woods J (eds) Handbook of the Philosophy of Science. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 311–334

  • Mossio M, Moreno A (2010) Organisational closure in biological organisms. Hist Philos Life Sci 32(2–3):269–288

    Google Scholar 

  • Nedelcu AM, Michod RE (2004) Evolvability, modularity, and individuality during the transition to multicellularity in volvocalean green algae. In: Schlosser G, Wagner G (eds) Modularity in development and evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 468–489

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliveri P, Tu Q, Davidson EH (2008) Global regulatory logic for specification of an embryonic cell lineage. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 105:5955–5962

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee HH (1973) The physical basis and origin of hierarchical control. In: Pattee HH (ed) Hierarchy theory. Braziller, New York, pp 73–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper JW, Herron MD (2008) Does biology need an organism concept? Biol Rev 83(4):621–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perlman RL (2000) The concept of the organism in physiology. Theory Biosci 119:174–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peter I, Davidson EH (2009) Genomic control of patterning. Int J Dev Biol 53:707–716

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peter I, Davidson EH (2010) The endoderm gene regulatory network in sea urchin embryos up to mid-blastula stage. Dev Biol 340(2):188–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peter I, Davidson EH (2011) A gene regulatory network controlling the embryonic specification of endoderm. Nature 474:635–639

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC, Strassmann JE (2009) Beyond society: the evolution of organismality. Philos Trans R Soc B Biol Sci 364:3143–3155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rokas A (2008) The origins of multicellularity and the early history of the genetic toolkit for animal development. Annu Rev Genet 42:235–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosslenbroich B (2009) The theory of increasing autonomy in evolution—a new proposal for understanding macroevolutionary innovations. Biol Philos 24:623–644

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Moreno A (2004) Basic autonomy as a fundamental step in the synthesis of life. Artif Life 10(3):235–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Moreno A (2011) Autonomy in evolution: from minimal to complex life. Synthese 185(1):21–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Etxeberria A, Moreno A, Ibáñez J (2000) Organisms and their place in biology. Theory Biosci 119:43–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Peretó J, Moreno A (2004) A universal definition of life: autonomy and open-ended evolution. Orig Life Evol Biosph 34(3):323–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Umerez J, Moreno A (2008) Enabling conditions for open-ended evolution. Biol Philos 23(1):67–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santelices B (1999) How many kinds of individual are there? Trends Ecol Evol 14(4):152–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith J, Theodoris C, Davidson EH (2007) A gene regulatory network subcircuit drives a dynamic pattern of gene expression. Science 318:794–797

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stelreny K, Griffiths PE (1999) Sex and death. An introduction to philosophy of biology. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Strassmann JE, Queller DC (2010) The social organism: congresses, parties and committees. Evolution 64(3):605–616

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turroni F, Ribbera A, Foroni E, van Sinderen D, Ventura M (2008) Human gut microbiota and bifidobacteria: from composition to functionality. Antonie Van Leeuwenhoek 94(1):35–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Kiers ET (2009) Evolution: what is an organism? Curr Biol 19(23):R1080–R1082

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson J (1999) Biological individuality. The individuation and persistence of living entities. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson J (2000) Ontological butchery: organism concepts and biological generalizations. Philos Sci 67:301–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS, Sober E (1989) Reviving the superorganism. J Theor Biol 136:337–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W (1974) Complexity and organization. In: Schaffner KF, Cohen RS (eds) PSA 1972. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, pp 67–86

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work has been supported by grants from the Ministerio de Ciencia e Innovación FFU2009-12895-CO2-02, Ministerio de Economía y Competitividad FFI2011-25665 and Gobierno Vasco IT 505-10. Argyris Arnellos holds a Marie Curie Research Fellowship (IEF-273635). We wish to thank the participants of the workshop on “Autonomy and Individual Organisms in Biology” (organized by the IAS-Research Centre in October 2012) and especially Laura Nuño de la Rosa and John Dupré for helpful discussions on the subject. Finally, we would like to thank the editor and two anonymous reviewers for useful suggestions that contributed to the improvement of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alvaro Moreno.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Arnellos, A., Moreno, A. & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. Organizational requirements for multicellular autonomy: insights from a comparative case study. Biol Philos 29, 851–884 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9387-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9387-x

Keywords

Navigation